2022, Vol. 66(2) 217 –245
What’s Fair in
International Politics?
Equity, Equality, and
Foreign Policy Attitudes
Kathleen E. Powers
1
, Joshua D. Kertzer
2
,
Deborah J. Brooks
1
, and Stephen G. Brooks
1
Abstract
How do concerns about fairness shape foreign policy preferences? In this article, we
show that fairness has two faces—one concerning equity, the other concerning
equality—and that taking both into account can shed light on the structure of
important foreign policy debates. Fielding an original survey on a national sample
of Americans, we show that different types of Americans think about fairness in
different ways, and that these fairness concerns shape foreign policy preferences:
individuals who emphasize equity are far more sensitive to concerns about burden
sharing, are far less likely to support US involvement abroad when other countries
aren’t paying their fair share, and often support systematically different foreign
policies than individuals who emphasize equality. As long as IR scholars focus only on
the equality dimension of fairness, we miss much about how fairness concerns
matter in world politics.
Keywords
public opinion about foreign policy, political psychology, fairness, burden sharing
1
Dartmouth College, Hanover, NH, USA
2
Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA
Corresponding Author:
Kathleen E. Powers, Dartmouth College, Department of Government 3 Tuck Mall, Hanover, NH 03755,
USA.
Journal of Conflict Resolution
ª The Author(s) 2021
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00220027211041393
journals.sagepub.com/home/jcr
Article
218 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
From alliance politics to climate change, many of the central challenges in interna-
tional politics today relate to questions of fairness. Superpowers who cont ribute
more to collective defense complain about burden sharing (Oneal 1990), while
rapidly growing economies like China bristle at the prospect of suffering dispropor-
tionate economic harm to protect the global environment. Fairness concerns pervade
territorial disputes (Goddard 2006), peace negotiations (Albin and Druckman 2012),
international cooperation (Kapstein 2008; Kertzer and Rathbun 2015; Efrat and
Newman 2016), and the domestic politics of crisis bargaining (Gottfried and Trager
2016). Among policymakers, fairness appears to be a bipartisan principle:
Democratic Presiden t Obama once declared that “free riders aggravate me” and
warned British Prime Minister David Cameron to “pay your fair share” in military
spending or risk the “special relationship.”
1
A few years later, Republican President
Trump echoed Obama’s concerns that NATO allies’ reliance on U.S. defense spend-
ing was simply “not fair”
2
while also decrying China’s “unfair trade practices.”
3
What makes a foreign policy action “unfair”? We argue that fairness has two
faces. IR scholars tend to discuss fairness primarily in terms of equality—in which
something is fair if everyone receives the same outcome (see, e.g., Baldwin 1993;
Albin and Druckman 2012; Kertzer and Rathbun 2015; Gottfried and Trager 2016).
This is consistent with a voluminous body of research on the ultimatum game, which
finds that players often reject offers that deviate from a 50-50 resource division
because unequal allocations are perceived as unfair (Gu
¨
th, Schmittberger, and
Schwarze 1982). The IR literature on relative gains reaches similar conclusions,
finding that actors dislike agreements that cause them to gain less than the other
side (Grieco 1988; Mutz and Kim 2017).
Yet equality is not the only criterion used to judge what’s “fair”—many actors are
also motivated to maintain equity. Equity implies that differential rewards are fair if
they are proportional to actors’ relative contributions (Adams 1965). Capturing this
distinction is especially important given ideological divides in American politics.
Although most Americans report a commitment to fairness in the abstract (Graham,
Haidt, and Nosek 2009), they disagree on what fairness looks like in practice, with
liberals expressing more concern about equality than conservatives, for example
(Haidt 2012; DeScioli et al. 2014; Jost, Federico, and Napier 2009; Meegan
2019). As Hochschild (1981) and Fiske and Tetlock (1997, 276) note, the tension
between these two fairness conceptions animates many of the key debates in
American political culture. Yet apart from research on inequity aversion in interna-
tional political economy (IPE; Lu
¨
, Scheve, and Slaughter 2012; Bechtel, Hainmuel-
ler, and Margalit 2017), IR scholars who invoke fairness have almost exclusively
focused on equality rather than equity, thereby neglecting fairness’ second face.
In this article, we argue that both equity and equality have important implications
for the study of international politics, and we seek to make three important contri-
butions to research on fairness in foreign policy. First, we introduce a new way to
measure individual differences in equity and equality concerns that we believe will
be useful for future research on fairness in both IR and political science more
2 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 219
generally. Since respondents can have different principles in mind when they report
that fairness matters using standard survey items (Rathbun, Powers, and Anders
2019), we elicit moral judgments about specific equity or equ ality violations in
everyday life. In an original national survey of American adults, we find that the
two faces of fairness form distinct factors: some Americans care about equity, some
care about equality, and some care about both.
Second, we show that the distinction between these two faces of fairness can help
explain debates in the United States about burden sharing. Although burden sharing
is one of the central dilemmas in contemporary foreign policy, looming large in
debates about the future direction of American grand strategy (S. G. Brooks and
Wohlforth 2016), climate policy negotiations (Bernauer, Gampfer, and Kachi 2014),
and global governance more generally, it is strangely understudied in American
public opinion about foreign policy. We show that individual differences in concerns
about equity meaningfully shape Americans’ attitudes about burden sharing in inter-
national politics, and can help explain the bipartisan aversion to disproportionate
U.S. contributions. These findings are consistent with bottom-up theories of public
opinion about foreign policy, offering another example of how personal values spill
over into the foreign policy domain (Rathbun et al. 2016; Kertzer and Zeitzoff
2017): the more concerned about equity individuals are in their daily lives, the more
they are bothered by burden sharing imbalances in foreign policy.
Finally, we turn to a broader selection of foreign policy issues. We show that
equality concerns are associated with support for policies that advance joint gains,
and equity concerns are associated with support for policies that maximize relative
gains. As a result, the effects of each face of fairness on foreign policy preferences
sometimes diverge: equality predicts support for free trade, for example, while
equity predicts support for protectionism, and these results hold even when control-
ling for partisanship or political ideology. Together, our results demonstrate that as
long as IR scholars primarily focus on a single equality dimension of fairness, and
associate fairness exclusively with prosociality, we miss much about how fairness
concerns shape foreign policy.
What’s Fair in Foreign Policy?
One of the central puzzles in the study of public opinion about foreign policy is how
the mass public comes to form its judgments about foreign policy issues, despite
knowing relatively little about international politics. The political science literature
on this subject has largely fallen into two camps. Some scholars offer top-down
models, in which members of the public overcome their uncertainty about foreign
policy issues by taking cues from trusted political elites, usually the leaders of their
preferred political party (e.g., Berinsky 2009; Baum and Potter 2015; Guisinger and
Saunders 2017). Others offer bottom-up models, in which members of the public
overcome their uncertainty about foreign policy issues by drawing on their basic
value systems or orientations (e.g., Hurwitz and Peffley 1987; Goren et al. 2016;
Powers et al. 3
220 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
Kertzer and Zeitzoff 2017). Unlike in top-down models, which assume citizens are
partisan but not ideological, bottom-up models argue that citizens have more
structured poli cy preferences than cynics suggest, because the same values that
shape our behavior in our pe rsonal lives als o shape our forei gn policy preferences
(Rathbun et al. 2016). People who care about retribution, for example, are more
likely to support punitive wars (Liberman 2006) and oppose unconditional finan-
cial bailouts (Rathbun, Powers, and Anders 2019). The value commitments that
predict our lifestyle choices or consumption behaviors also predict our foreign
policy preferences (Cohrs et al. 2005; Kertzer et al. 2014; Bayram 2015; Kreps
and Maxey 2018).
One value that occupies a prominent place in this literature—and in the psychol-
ogy of morality more generally—is fairness (e.g., Graham, Haidt, and Nosek 2009;
Rai and Fiske 2011; Meegan 2019). Concerns about fairness are usually seen as
having evolutionary origins: people must be able to detect and punish cheaters if
they want to enjoy the spoils from cooperation and guard themselves against exploi-
tatio n (Hai dt 2012), and fairness concerns typically begin to appear in children
around the age of five (Fehr, Bernhard, and Rockenbach 2008). Political scientists
have thus linked fairness concerns to a range of phenomena in international politics,
including crisis bargaining (Gottfried and Trager 2016), post-war peace negotiations
(Albin and Druckman 2012), diplomacy (Kertzer and Rathbun 2015), international
humanitarian law (Chu 2019), international cooperation (Efrat and Newman 2016),
and foreign direct investment (Chilton, Milner, and Tingley 2020).
What IR scholars have neglected, however, is that “fairness” carries multiple
meanings, based on different moral principles (Hochschild 1981; Rasinski 1987;
Jennings 1991; Trump 2018; Brutger and Rathbun 2020). While there are debates in
both normative and empirical research about the number of distinct allocation prin-
ciples (Deutsch 1975; Scott et al. 2001), for our purposes we follow Rasinski (1987)
in focusing on two principles in particular: equality and equity.
Equality implies a concern with egalitarian outcomes: an agreement or distribu-
tion is fair when actors attain equivalent end-states. Behavioral economic games
routine ly find that participants prefer resources to be distributed equally among
players (e.g., Gu
¨
th, Schmittberger, and Schwarze 1982; Thaler 1988; Fehr and
Schmidt 1999). In ultimatum games where initial endowments are fixed by the
experimenter, for example, receivers usually “put their money where their mouth
is” and reject unequal offers from proposers (Camerer 1997, 169), choosing to
receive nothing at all rather than accept less than 50 percent of the pot.
4
Other
research illustrates that equality-minded individuals support policies that promote
symmetric outcomes without regard to whether some beneficiaries contribute more
resources than others. In American politics, for example, concerns about equality
tend to be linked with support for social programs like welfare (Feldman and Zaller
1992). The same pattern applies in an IR context: If the purpose of an alliance is to
ensure equal security for all parties, the “fairest” arrangement might require wealthy
members like the U.S. to spend more than their poorer allies.
4 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 221
Equity, in contrast, shifts the focus from outcomes to inputs. Equity implies a
concern with proportionality: resource allocations should account for beneficiaries’
perceived contributions (Rai and Fiske 2011). Individuals who value equity believe
that people ought to reap what they sow.
5
The actor who contributes more to a
common resource merits a bigger slice of the pie: according to the equity principle,
actors’ payoffs should be proportionate to their effort (Adams 1965; DeScioli et al.
2014). Inequity occurs when individuals share a resource but some beneficiaries
shoulder more of a burden for supplying it. Demands that welfare recipients work to
receive benefits often invoke equity principles, for example, and research on
free-riding demonstrates that equity violations plague social dilemmas (Ostrom
1998). Fuhrmann (2020) describes how weaker states in an alliance have incentives
to free-ride because they can benefit from collective deterrence while powerful allies
like the U.S. pay the costs. When policymakers protest that it is unfair for some
NATO members to dedicate the requisite 2 percent of their GDP to defense while
others spend less but receive the same security benefits from the alliance, they call
attention to inequity. Free-riding is common, but inequitable.
6
Despite evidence that people evaluate fairness in terms of both equality and
equity, IR scholarship almost exclusively focuses on the former. When Albin
and Druckman (2012), for example, find that “just” civil war settlements are
more durable than their unfair counterparts, they focus on the distributive justice
principle of equality. Former belligerents prefer agreement s that provide equal
rights for citizens of all parties to the agreement alongside equal political power.
Efrat and Newman (2016) similarly rely on equality when they argue that states
will be more likely to defer child abduction cases to partners whose legal
systems are fair. In public opinion, Kertzer et al. (2014), Kreps and Maxey
(2018), and Cram et al. (2018) similarly define fairness in terms of equal treatment
for individuals.
Equality’s privileged place in research on fairness in IR is significant for several
reasons.
7
First, we know that equity and equality tend to dominate in different
domains in domestic politics—equality reigns in the family, but equity in the mar-
ketplace, for example (Hochschild 1981; Jennings 1991), such that splitting food
equally tend s to be considered fair, while splitting money equally regardless of
contribution is not (DeVoe and Iyengar 2010). But we have little sense of when
each principle dominates in the foreign policy realm.
Second, those few IR scholars who do study equity tend to treat equity prefer-
ences as a constant, rather a variable. Scholarship on inequity aversion in IPE
assumes that everyone bristles at inequity ( Lu
¨
, Scheve, and Slaughter 2012;
Bechtel, Hainmueller, and Margalit 2017). Yet an ever-growing body of psychology
research tells us that people vary in their commitment to moral principles (Graham,
Haidt, and Nosek 2009). Consistent with research on the role of equality in foreign
policy public opinion (Kertzer et al. 2014), we can treat equity concerns as an
individual difference, asking not just whether equity matters, but for whom. Like
the business-minded leaders in Fuhrmann’s (2020) research on free-riding, some
Powers et al. 5
222 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
members of the public might be especially sensitive to imbalances between inputs
and outcomes.
Third, and related, research in social psychology shows that liberals value equal-
ity more than their conservative counterparts (Haidt 2012; Starmans, Sheskin, and
Bloom 2017; Meindl, Iyer, and Graham 2019). When conservatives invoke fairness
in domestic politics, they tend to be concerned primarily with whether those who
work hard or pay more taxes reap appropriate rewards, whereas liberals emphasize
both equity and equality, hoping to advance societal well-being by meeting every-
one’s basic needs. This distinction illuminates partisan differences about welfare
work requirements, for example, but also clarifies important areas of convergence
such as the widespread support for social security across the ideological spectrum:
working Americans all “pay in” but the program provides some financial stability
for all citizens (Haidt 2013; Meegan 2019). Disaggregating fairness also enriches
our u nderstanding of how fairness s hapes foreign policy attitudes. If equality is
primarily a liberal value, but equity matters to Americans across the ideological
spectrum, we can make sense of the cross-partisan nature of complaints about
free-riding in U.S. foreign policy. Moreover, psychologists have also found gender
differences in fairness preferences: whether due to structural societal differences or
early childhood socialization, women often display stronger preferences for equality
than men do (Rasinski 1987; Scott et al. 2001). If fairness attitudes are correlated
with distinctive foreign policy preferences, the tension between these competing
fairness principles could explain part of the gender gap in public opinion about
foreign affairs (D. J. B rooks and Valentino 2011; Mansfield, Mutz, and Silver
2015; Eichenberg and Stoll 2012; Lizotte 2019).
Our initial goal, then, is to replicate existing findings in the psychological liter-
ature with additional evidence that different types of Americans think about fairness
in different ways: to demonstrate that equity and equality are distinct moral princi-
ples, and to map constituencies that support each face of fairness. These considera-
tions lead to our first hypothesis:
Hypothesis 1: Fairness has two faces, with equality and equity forming distinct
dimensions.
Support for Hypothesis 1 would largely confirm previous work, though we intro-
duce a new way to measure individual differences in these distinct dimensions of
fairness. But we further claim that both faces of fairness matter for foreign policy
preferences in different ways. IR scholars often portray fairness as a prosocial value
that inspires international cooperation by promoting positive reciprocity (Kertzer
et al. 2014; Kertzer and Rathbun 2015), but this expectation only holds if we limit
our understanding of fairness to equality. Because equality-minded Americans prior-
itize outcomes, they are inclined toward foreign policies that maximize jointly
enjoyed gains and improve global conditions. In pursuit of parity, they set aside
egoistic concerns about the U.S.’s return on their foreign policy investments—like
6 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 223
whether the U.S. gains more relative to other states or contributes more resources
than its partners in pursuit of just, egalitarian ends.
8
The U.S. can contribute to
egalitarian outcomes by working through international institutions like the UN,
providing foreign aid to developing countries, or helping to clean up the g lobal
environment so that everyone has equal access to clean air. Each policy is compa-
tible with an equality principle: The fact that the U.S. might be required to contribute
more to institutions, aid, or environmental protectio n than other states d oes not
undermine fairness when it is defined as equality. This logic explains why previous
research reports a relationship between fairness values and cooperative internation-
alism (Kertzer et al. 2014), or between equality-oriented predispositions like Social
Dominance Orientation and support for trade agreements that maximize joint rather
than relative gains (Mutz and Kim 2017).
By contrast, equity-oriented individuals attend to the cost side of the equation.
Just as research on retribution demonstrates how concerns about justice can lead to
aggression (Liberman 2006; Rathbun and Stein 2020), we argue that equity-minded
Americans will oppose international cooperation on the basis of fairness. Equity
does not imply prosociality. An equity principle demands that actors receive rewards
that reflect their relative contributions, a situation that rarely obtains when the U.S.
responds to distant global problems.
We therefore expect that compared to equality, equity concerns will be strongly
associated with negative evaluations of burden sharing problems in international
politics in particular, and with opposition to policies that do not strike a balance
between the price the U.S. pays and the direct benefits it receives in general. Insofar
as concerns about free-riding dominate debates about everything from NATO con-
tributions to humanitarian interventions, financial bailouts, and climate change
negotiations, we miss out on important dynamics in world politics if we measure
only one face of fairness. Moreover, when a policy promi ses global or indirec t
benefits at a high cost to the U.S., the two faces of fairness will diverge—equality
will be associated with support whereas equity will be associated with opposition.
Together, these theoretical insights lead to two additional hypotheses:
Hypothesis 2: Equity is associated with concerns about burden sharing in
foreign policy.
Hypothesis 3: Equality is associated with support for policies that maximize
jointly enjoyed gains, while equity is associated with support for policies that
maximize relative gains.
Methods and Results
To demonstrate the value of studying both faces of fairness in IR, we conducted an
original survey in August 2014 on a national sample of 1,073 Americans recruited
through Survey Sampling International (SSI). Participants, 69.5 percent of whom
identified as white and 51.3 percent of whom identified as female, ranged in age
Powers et al. 7
224 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
from 19 to 95 (median: 49) and reported a median household income of $50 to
60,000. SSI employs an opt-in method to recruit a panel of participants targeted to
census quotas for sex, age, race, and region; Table 1 in Online Appendix §1.2 shows
the sample matches census targets on key demographic characteristics.
9
We present our analysis in three stages. First, we introduce our measurement
strategy to show that Americans differentiate between equity and equality when they
make judgments about right and wrong, and that Americans from both ends of the
political sp ectrum value equity. Second, we show that variations in Americans’
equity commitments can help explain the polarized debates in the United States
about burden sharing in American foreign policy. Third, we analyze a series of
Table 1. Fairness Vignettes: To What Extent Does Each Scenario Feel Morally Wrong?
Violates Factor loadings
Scenario Equity Equality Mean (SD) PA1 PA2
1 A student copies another student’s work on
an ungraded assignment. (Copies Ungraded)
Y N 5.69 (1.54) 0.679
2 A student copies another student’s work and
gets the same grade. (Copies Graded)
Y N 6.12 (1.33) 0.862
3 A runner takes a shortcut on the course
during a marathon. (Marathon Shortcut)
Y N 6.09 (1.36) 0.829
4 Two brothers win the lottery with a ticket
they bought together, but the earnings
aren’t divided evenly. (Lottery Division)
Y Y 5.75 (1.57) 0.566 0.212
5 A girl takes all of the Halloween candy from
a bowl, leaving none for others.
(Halloween Candy)
Y Y 5.76 (1.49) 0.653 0.17
6 A raise is given to a worker, when another
worker needs it more. (Raise for One
Worker)
N Y 3.71 (1.9) 0.83
7 An employee earns a lot of money while
another earns very little. (Employee
Earns More)
N Y 4.10 (1.96) 0.812
Note: All items range from 1 to 7, with higher values indicating that the situation feels more morally
wrong. The second and third columns indicate whether the scenario involves an equity violation (in which
the outcome is not proportional to the inputs), an equality violation (in which the outcomes are
inegalitarian), or both; the first three scenarios violate equity but not equality, the last two scenarios
violate equality but not equity, and two scenarios (Lottery Division and Halloween Candy) violate both. The
table shows two key findings. First, scenarios that include an equity violation are seen as substantially
more morally wrong than scenarios that do not, showcasing the importance of equity in our moral
judgments. Second, the results from an exploratory factor analysis show that a two-factor solution maps
onto our theoretical codings, with one factor referring to equity, and the other to equality. Interestingly,
the two scenarios that include both equity and equality violations show some weak cross-loading, but
ultimately load on the equity factor rather than the equality factor, suggesting that the equity concerns are
more salient.
8 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 225
broader foreign policy issues to show that the effects of equity and equality some-
times diverge, with concerns about equality associated with support for policies that
maximize global gains, and concerns about equity associated with policies that
maximize relative gains. These results highlight why scholars need to consider both
faces of fairness in research on public opinion in foreign policy.
Differentiating between Two Faces of Fairness
Although political scientists sometimes use the Moral Foundations Questionnaire
(MFQ) to study the extent to which individuals care about people being “treated
fairly” (Graham, Haidt, and Nosek 2009), our purposes preclude this and similar
scales because the meaning of “fairness” here is itself ambiguous: participants could
interpret “fair” treatment as equity, equality, or both—leaving us uncertain of which
construct we are measuring (Rathbun, Powers, and Anders 2019; Brutger and Rath-
bun 2020). A key goal of this paper is to develop an alternative measurement scale
that can usefully distinguish between equity and equality for future political science
research.
We therefore build on Clifford et al. (2015, 1179), which develops a series of
“moral foundations vignettes” to assess individuals’ moral co mmitments. Each
vignette describes a situation in which an actor violates some moral principle, and
asks respondents to evaluate whether the action feels morally wrong. The vignettes
are designed both to depict violations of one value at a time, such that ideal items
will discriminate between even closely related moral principles, and to distinguish
moral violations from social norms. For example, the fairness vignettes avoid refer-
ences to (1) physical or emotional harm, which taps the harm/care foundation,
(2) hierarchical relationships, lest they invoke authority values, and (3) “race, gen-
der, or structural equality” because these characteristics are more likely to tap other,
non-moral, attitudes (Clifford et al. 2015, 1181).
10
Clifford et al. (2015, 1179) note
that the moral foundations scale “relies on respondents’ rating of abstract principles,
rather than judgment of concrete scenarios,” and that abstract endorsements may not
always translate into political attitudes. The vignettes allow us to probe concrete
moral judgments, but in scenarios taken from everyday life, rather than politics or
foreign policy.
Table 1 displays the seven vignettes we employ to measure fairness attitudes,
building on the fairness inventories established by Clifford et al. (2015), Iyer (2010),
and Meindl, Iyer, and Graham (2019). For each vignette, participants indicated the
extent to which the situation felt morally wrong on a seven-point scale from “not at
all wrong” to “extremely wrong.” The first three vignettes in Table 1 depict clear
equity violations, where individuals receive outcomes that are not proportionate to
the inputs they provide. For example, “A student copies another student’s work and
gets the same grade,” or “A runner takes a shortcut on the course during a marathon”
both describe outcomes that do not accurately correspond to individuals’ contribu-
tions. These scenarios are not problematic on equality principles (we don’t care
Powers et al. 9
226 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
about guaranteeing equality of outcomes when evaluating assignments, or on a race
course) but are problematic on equity principles (we expect that individuals who
perform better will be rewarded as such).
The last two vignettes capture clear equality violations, where actors fail to attain
equivalent end-states. It might be considered fair from an equity perspective when
“An employee earns a lot of money while another earns very little” (since under
equity principles, earnings can be guided by merit), but this asymmetry in wages is
considered unfair from an equality perspective (Meindl, Iyer, and Graham 2019).
Finally , two of the vig nettes depict a violation both of equity principles and of
equality principles. In the lottery division scenario (“Two brothers win the lottery
with a ticket they bought together, but the earnings aren’t divided evenly”), the
uneven division of the winnings not only represents an equality violation, but also
an equity violation, since the two brothers bought the ticket together. In the hallow-
een candy scenario (“A girl takes all of the halloween candy from a bowl, leaving
none for others”), the girl who absconds with the candy not only fails to split it
evenly with others (an equality violation), but given the lack of information indi-
cating she was the one who provided all of the candy in the first place, likely takes a
haul that is disproportionate to her contributions (an equity violation).
Two additional points are worth noting about Table 1. First, the table presents
basic descriptive statistics for each vignette. Although the means for most of the
items are relatively high—consistent with extensive research showing that fairness is
an important moral principle for most Americans (Graham, Haidt, and Nosek 2009;
Haidt 2013)—some are substantially higher than others: scenarios that include an
equity violation are seen by our respondents as more morally wrong than scenarios
that do not, showcasing the importance of equity in our moral judgments.
Second, we conducted an exploratory factor analysis (EFA) on the fairness vign-
ettes. If fairness is unidimensional—if moral judgments about fairness violations
depend on a single principle—we would find that one factor explains most of the
common variance in the data. Instead, parallel analysis and model fit statistics
suggest a two factor solution, which fits the data well (TLI¼0:93, RMSEA¼0:09).
11
We therefore estimate a two factor solution using principal axis factor analysis with
oblimin rotation, producing the factor loadings in the two right-hand columns of
Table 1. Consistent with Hypothesis 1, the results show that the first three vignettes,
which violate equity principles, load on a single factor; the last two items, which
violate equality principles, load on the other factor. And, of particular interest, the
two items that feature both equity and equality violations cross-load on both factors,
but ultimately display stronger loadings on the equity factor than the equality factor.
This finding suggests that respondents confronted with bo th equity and equal ity
violations found the equity concerns in these scenarios to be more salient, and
reinforces the importance of taking fairness’ second face into account.
To obtain respondent-level measures for sensitivity to different types of fairness
concerns, we extract factor scores from the factor analysis and produce latent mea-
sures for concerns about equity (mean ¼ 0:82, sd ¼ 0:19) and concerns about
10 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 227
equality (mean ¼ 0:5, sd ¼ 0:26).
12
Figure 1 displays the density distributions for
equity and equality across partisan and ideological categories. What is striking is just
how widespread concerns about equity are. For each constituency, equity trumps
equality, and the results are also relatively stable across partisan and ideological
subgroups: conservatives value equity more than liberals do (t ¼�2:54, p < 0:05),
but the substantive size of the difference is relatively small.
13
In contrast, we find
both ideological and partisan divides on equality: Democrats care more about
outcome-oriented equality violations than their Republican counterparts (t ¼ 6:8,
p < 0:01), and liberals more than conservatives (t ¼ 3:85, p < 0:01). This pattern is
consistent with what psychologists recognize as a key line dividing ideas about
Female Male
Liberal Moderate Conservative
Democrat Independent Republican
0.00 0.25 0.50 0.75 1.00 0.00 0.25 0.50 0.75 1.00
0.00 0.25 0.50 0.75 1.00
Density
Fairness type
Equality
Equity
Figure 1. Strong concerns about equity across demographic groups.
Note: Figure 1 displays density distributions for equity and equality across party identification, ideology,
and gender. The plots show that both the left and right value equity, whereas left-leaning respondents
place a heavier emphasis on equality than right-leaning ones do. Women care more about both types of
fairness than men do.
Powers et al. 11
228 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
fairness in American politics (Haidt 2013; Clifford et al. 2015; Meegan 2019).
Multiple group factor analysis in Online Appendix §2.3 further confirms that Dem-
ocrats and Republicans think about fairness in slightly different ways: although we
obtain the same factor solution in both groups, we also find that the two latent factors
are moderately correlated among Democrats (r ¼ 0:30), but not among Republicans
(r ¼ 0:01): Democrats who care more about equity tend to also care more about
equality, but the same is not true for their Republican counterparts.
Finally, we find even starker differences with respect to gender. Women care
significantly more about fairness violations than men do, both for equity (t ¼ 4:439,
p < 0:01) and equality (t ¼ 4:22, p < 0:01). These patterns highlight the cost of
privileging equality in research on fairness in IR. Equality alone cannot capture how
Americans think about fairness and in fact, appears to be a significantly weaker
concern than equity, even among liberals. Next, we examine how these different
types of fairness concerns are associated with foreign policy preferences.
Equity Predicts Opposition to Burden Sharing Violations
Our initial findings show that most Americans value equity. We therefore turn to a
specific class of foreign policy issues where we expect this type of moral principle to
loom particularly large: burden sharing. Despite the fact that burden sharing con-
cerns animate contemporary debates about the most consequential foreign policy
issues from NATO to the Paris Climate Agreement, they are rarely included in
standard measures of foreign policy attitudes (e.g., Hurwitz and Peffley 1987;
Chittick, Billingsley, and Travis 1995; Rathbun et al. 2016; Gravelle, Reifler, and
Scotto 2017). We argue that when members of the public decry actions in which the
U.S. bears disproportionately large costs, they transfer their general concern for
equity in their daily lives to the foreign policy domain.
Our four dependent variable questions solicit individual reactions to common
scenarios in which the U.S. makes a substantial contribution to resolve a collective
problem. Participants responded to four hypothetical foreign engagements and rated
the extent to which each poses a problem for the U.S. on a scale from 1 (“not a
problem at all”) to 7 (“a very big problem”). Each item, listed in Table 2, describes a
different substantive domain in which the U.S. plays a dominant role in resolving a
collective problem. Defense Budgets, for example, implicates U.S. allies who ear-
mark fewer resources for defense, while Enviro nment introduces a hypothetical
scenario in which the U.S. foots the bill for an environmental disaster in international
waters. The scenarios each highlight the concerns about proportionality that plague
foreign policy questions across issue areas. In creating the four scenarios, we aim to
capture a set of problems that implicate equity and demonstrate its important role in
foreign policy public opinion. We turn to a broader set of foreign policy problems
that implicate both equity and equality in a subsequent section below.
In addition to factor scores for equity and equality, our primary independent
variables, we control for three widely-used scales for foreign policy
12 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 229
orientations—militant internationalism, cooperative internationalism, and isolation-
ism (Wittkopf 1990). Militant internationalism (MI) refers to an inclination to use
force to achieve foreign policy goals, and emphasizes the importance of demonstrat-
ing military resolve. This measure of military assertiveness thus taps the familiar
distinction between foreign policy hawks and doves. Cooperative internationalism
(CI) captures the extent to which individuals want the U.S. to work with other states
and international institutions to solve global problems like climate change (Wittkopf
1990). It entails a commitment to global participation but not to military force. For
isolationism, we include a scale that taps this general preference for disengagement
from the world—a stance that maintains that America should “come home” and
scale down its conception of itself as a leader (Chittick, Billingsley, and Travis
1995).
Finally, we included a battery of demographic questions alongside measures of
partisanship and ideology. Participants report their age, sex, race, education attain-
ment (from less than high school to Post-graduate), income (split into quartiles for
analysis), and U.S. region of residence (midwest, northeast, south, or west). We
measure self-reported partisanship with a seven-point scale where a 7 indicates
strong Republican, and ideology on a seven-point scale from extremely liberal to
extremely conservative. The fairness vignettes, burden sharing violations, foreign
policy orientations, and demographics appeared in separate, randomly ordered
blocks.
Table 3 presents estimates from a series of OLS regression models that predict
responses to the four burden sharing vignettes. The dependent measures and con-
tinuous independent variables have been rescaled from 0 to 1, and higher values
indicate that participants rated the scenario a bigger problem for the United States.
Positive coefficients suggest that stronger commitments to the moral principle are
associated with less support for America taking on an “unfair” global burden. Mod-
els 2, 4, 6, and 8 include foreign policy orientations and demographic controls.
Consistent with H2, equity is a statistically and substantively important predictor
of attitudes toward U.S. contributions to global problems. The extent to which
Table 2. Burden Sharing Scenarios: How Much of a Problem Is Each for the United States?
Countries such as Germany, Canada, and Japan devote a far smaller share of their economy to
defense spending than the United States does, because they are US allies and America has
pledged to defend them. (Defense Budgets)
Western allies give less foreign aid to provide for education and health care for women and
children in the Middle East, because they know the US will foot the bill. (Foreign Aid)
The US provides all of the needed troops and money for a peacekeeping mission while other
countries do not contribute any troops or money to the mission. (Peacekeeping)
The US provides all of the needed resources and personnel for cleaning up toxic waste
contamination from a sunken ship in Antarctica while other countries do not contribute
any resources or personnel to the effort. (Environment)
Powers et al. 13
230 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
Table 3. Americans High in Equity Preferences Tend to be More Concerned about Burden Sharing Violations in US Foreign Policy.
Domain of Burden sharing Violation:
Defense Budgets Peacekeeping Environment Foreign Aid
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8)
Equity 0.325*** 0.281*** 0.469*** 0.376*** 0.453*** 0.396*** 0.468*** 0.384***
(0.044) (0.047) (0.041) (0.043) (0.041) (0.044) (0.041) (0.044)
Equality 0.119*** 0.119*** 0.007 0.010 0.054* 0.058* 0.022 0.029
(0.033) (0.035) (0.030) (0.032) (0.030) (0.032) (0.031) (0.032)
Cooperative Int. 0.076 0.032 0.053 0.012
(0.046) (0.042) (0.043) (0.043)
Militant Int. 0.049 0.022 0.066 0.118***
(0.047) (0.042) (0.043) (0.043)
Isolationism 0.175*** 0.172*** 0.154*** 0.169***
(0.039) (0.035) (0.036) (0.036)
Male 0.023 0.038** 0.027* 0.027*
(0.017) (0.016) (0.016) (0.016)
White 0.002 0.015 0.017 0.037*
(0.021) (0.019) (0.020) (0.020)
Age 0.001** 0.003*** 0.001*** 0.002***
(0.001) (0.001) (0.001) (0.001)
Some College 0.011 0.019 0.023 0.026
(0.024) (0.022) (0.022) (0.023)
College 0.011 0.019 0.003 0.021
(0.023) (0.021) (0.021) (0.021)
Post-Graduate 0.007 0.012 0.011 0.004
(0.031) (0.028) (0.028) (0.029)
Income: $30–60,000 0.009 0.004 0.001 0.009
(continued)
14
Powers et al. 231
Table 3. (continued)
Domain of Burden sharing Violation:
Defense Budgets Peacekeeping Environment Foreign Aid
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8)
(0.022) (0.020) (0.020) (0.020)
Income: $60–100,000 0.005 0.005 0.008 0.010
(0.023) (0.021) (0.021) (0.021)
Income: > $100,000 0.026 0.003 0.003 0.017
(0.026) (0.024) (0.024) (0.024)
Region Controls PP P PPPPP
Constant 0.317*** 0.203*** 0.361*** 0.222*** 0.298*** 0.161*** 0.324*** 0.082
(0.038) (0.066) (0.035) (0.060) (0.035) (0.061) (0.035) (0.061)
N 1,002 997 1,002 997 1,002 997 1,001 996
R
2
0.075 0.109 0.121 0.181 0.123 0.163 0.121 0.171
Note: Table displays OLS coefficients, standard errors in parentheses. Higher values indicate participants rated the scenario a bigger problem for the US. All continuous
variables, except age, have been rescaled from 0 to 1. Reference categories are <$30,000, High school or less, and West.
*p < .1.
**p < .05.
***p < .01.
15
232 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
individuals believe that input/output ratios dictate whether an action should be
deemed moral or immoral predicts their view of whether certain foreign policy
activities are justifiable. Indeed, the environment, foreign aid, and peacekeep ing
vignettes draw almost exclusively on equity concerns—not equality. In the case
of environmental cleanup in Antarctica, a move from the minimum to the maximum
on equity is associated with a 0.453-unit increase in the policy preferences—a shift
in nearly half the 0 to 1 scale. Since Antarctica does not belong to just one state, the
cleanup arguably benefits all global actors. Like President George W. Bush, who
avowed that he would not “let the United States carry the burden for cleaning up the
world’s air,” equity-minded citizens think that other states should contribute if they
expect to reap the rewards from a clean environment.
14
The same logic underlies the strong association between equity and foreign aid.
Because allies know that the U.S. will provide long run development benefits
abroad, they shirk the opportunity to contribute a share proportionate to their GDP
or relative interest in the positive externalities associated with advancing women’s
healthcare. As participants’ moral commitment to equity increases, so does their
disdain for this foreign aid arrangement (b ¼ 0:468, p < 0:01). Peacekeeping mis-
sions have similarly concentrated benefits, such that equity values predict negative
perceptions of America taking the primary role in bearing the costs. A two standard
deviation increase in equity (sd ¼ 0:19) is associated with a 0.18-unit increase in
judgments that it is a problem for the U.S. if other states to not contribute to a
mission.
In contrast, equality plays a relatively smaller role: The coefficient for equality is
statistically significan t in Model 5—the environment vignett e (p < 0:1), but the
effect is substantively small. A move from the minimum to the maximum predicts
a 0.054 increase in the dependent measure, just a fraction of a step on the seven-point
scale. This is striking given the attention paid to fairness as primarily a value that
promotes individual rights in both political science scholarship (Jost, Federico, and
Napier 2009) and psychological research on moral foundations (Graham, Haidt, and
Nosek 2009).
Only burden sharing in security alliances—Models 1 and 2—seems to draw
significant opposition on the basis of both equity and equality. A move from the
minimum to the maximum on the equity dimension of fairness predicts a 0.325-unit
increase in reporting that disproportionate defense spending is a problem for the
United States. Allies contribute relatively less as a share of their GDP, and yet
benefit greatly from U.S. protection. At the same time, there are disparate outcomes
to consider if the U.S. is not equally secure as a consequence of their alliances. The
positive coefficient on equality bears out this relationship.
Models 2, 4, 6, and 8 include three foreign policy orientations frequently
identified as the main organizing structures for foreign policy attitudes (Gravelle,
Reifler, and Scotto 2017) alongside demographic controls. Of the three orientations,
only isolationism has a consistent and statistically significant relationship with the
dependent variables. Isolationist participants report that it is problematic for the U.S.
16 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 233
to act as the primary contributor to resolving any of the four international problems.
Cooperative and militant internationalism have little bearing on how participants
judge America’s unfair burdens. Importantly, the effects of equity are substantively
larger than isolationism. For example, a shift from the minimum to the maximum on
isolationism predicts a 0.172-unit increase in the assessment that it is a problem for
the U.S. to contribute all resources to peacekeeping mission. In contrast, a shift from
the minimum to maximum on equity is associated with a 0.376-unit increase in the
DV—twice the size of isolationism’s effect.
The results presented in Table 3 demonstrate that Americans who care about
equity express significantly greater concern about foreign policy scenarios in
which the U.S. contributes more than they benefit. This pattern holds across four
diverse policy domains and when we control for a range of foreign policy orien-
tations and demographic variables. The effect of equality, however, is less con-
sistent—the moral commitment to equal outcomes held by many left-leaning
Americans predicts attitudes toward defense spending but not other forms of
cooperation. The fact that equity continues to exert a substantively large effect
on burden sharing attitudes even controlling for foreign policy orientations like
isolationism is important: it shows that there is a class of individuals who are not
necessarily predisposed to want the US to stay home and focus more on its own
problems, but who are aggravated by other countries not pulling their weight.
Moreover, we fielded this study in 2014, well before Donald Trump and the
Republican party began amplifying concerns about “unfair” trade deals and alli-
ance arrangements, suggesting that our results are unlikely to be the artifact of
elite cues.
In Online Appendix §2.1, we conduct a variety of additional robustness checks,
showing that the stronger findings for equity in our results are not due to asymme-
tries in scale length, and that the pattern of results we report here are not merely an
artifact of broader ideological or partisan differences: equity retains its substantively
large and statistically significant effect on burden sharing concerns even when
controlling for partisanship and political ideology. Finally, we test for the possibility
that the fairness vignettes primed participants to adopt an equity lens when they
considered burden sharing violations. We find no evidence for order effects, miti-
gating this concern. Together, these findings offer another example of how personal
values spill over into foreign policy preferences (Rathbun et al. 2016): the more
individuals are offended by equity violations in their daily lives, the more concerned
they are about burden sharing in foreign policy, whether in terms of allies’ defense
budgets or foreign aid, peacekeeping or the environment.
Equity and Equality Shape Foreign Policy Attitudes beyond Burden Sharing
Our results show that equity values—but not equality values—are important for
understanding divergent reactions in the United States toward burden sharing in
foreign policy. Given the extent to which burden sharing issues feature prominently
Powers et al. 17
234 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
in contemporary foreign policy debates, but are somewhat understudied in the aca-
demic literature on public opinion about foreign policy, these findings make an
important contribution. However, one concern about this analysis is that the outcome
variables uniquely implicate equity—the DV question itself makes U.S. costs salient
by asking people whether the situation is a problem for the U.S.—and thereby mask
the important role of equality. In this section, we therefore measure support for a
broader set of concrete foreign policy proposals and probe the conditions under
which the two faces of fairness complement or contradict each other.
We measure support for three policy proposals, each of which implicates a
potential mismatch between U.S. contributions and the policy’s primary benefici-
aries abroad in a different domain of foreign affairs: international political economy,
international cooperation, and defense. The first proposal asks participants whether
they support or oppose decreasing limits on imports of foreign-made products, and
signing more free trade agreements like NAFTA (Free Trade).
15
We expect that
equality will predict support for this proposal, because free trade agreements level
the playing field for foreign companies and economies by allowing them to compete
for American business. Regional trade agreements like NAFTA can produce larger
gains for Mexico than for the U.S., but Americans who value equality view closing
the economic gap between developed and developing states as a desirable end.
16
Our
values shape whether we paint free trade as fair trade. By contrast, equity-minded
Americans might oppose free trade agreements that could damage some sectors of
the U.S. economy and improve trading partners’ overall welfare to a greater extent
than America’s. In turn, equity would predict less support for the Free Trade pro-
posal. Yet others might view competitive markets as inherently equitable, because
free markets enable actors to reap proportionate gains for their work. We consider
these competing expectations for equity in our analysis.
The second proposal asks participants whether they support an arms control treaty
that would reduce both US and Russian nuclear arsenals (Arms Control). We expect
a positive relationship between equality and support for this proposed treaty, which
offers global benefits: the potential for consequential accidents declines alongside
the number of nuclear weapons (Sagan 1995). Equity-minded participants, however,
will attend to the costs associated with arms control. The U.S. and Russia will each
witness a small decrease in their overall power. Some people who value equity might
think that this is a “fair” price to pay for the security the U.S. will gain from a smaller
Russian stockpile. But the proposal lacks information about the U.S. and Russia’s
respective starting positions, which could arouse relative gains concerns among
those who view equal reductions as inequitable—driving opposition. These con-
cerns muddy our expectations about how equity relates to support for arms control.
Finally, we ask participants if they support increasing military spending to allow
the US to better solve international problems (Military Spending). Again, this pro-
posal presents clear global benefits—to the extent that deploying the U.S. military
augurs peace, equality-minded Americans will be eager to invest. Viewed in a
different light, though, the proposal requires the U.S. to invest scarce economic
18 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 235
resources into a program that only benefits national security via indirect routes:
“Solving global problems” can bolster U.S. security in the long run, but the descrip-
tion emphasizes those benefits that accrue to the world. Much like our burden
sharing scenarios, this proposal asks the U.S. to pay while others reap the
rewards—driving equity-based opposition.
Each of these proposals entail ambiguous framing relative to the burden sharing
vignettes. They describe a plan, but leave room for participants to gauge the
distribution of costs and benefits associ ated with implementing the policy. This
ambiguity creates conceptual distance between our independent and dependent
variables and allows us to test out theory’s implications for a broader range of
issues. But it also limits our ability to parse fairness from partisanship if party
identification partly colors which face of fairness a proposal evokes. For example,
Republicans might focus on the equity-reducing prospects for n ew trade agree-
ments, whereas Democrats might look at the same proposal and think of the
implications for global equality. C ontrolling for partisanship cannot account for
this subtler pathway for confounding, whereby partisanship shapes the relative
salience of different policy aspects. Our analysis proceeds w ith this important
caution in mind.
Figure 2 presents estimates from a series of OLS models that estimate the rela-
tionship between equity, equa l ity, and support for each policy proposal. Each
model also controls for militant/cooperative internationalism and isola tionism—
coefficients depicted for comparison—and demographic variables.
17
The results
point to five key conclusions. First, consistent with Hypothesis 3, the two faces of
fairness are not always complementary. Whereas equality values are associated with
more support for military spending and free trade, equity-minded Americans would
rather not sacrifice resources if U.S. contributions outstrip whatever benefits the
U.S. stands to gain. Rather than increase foreign competition for Americans’ busi-
ness, equity-minded Americans prefer to reserve their home market for domestic
producers—perhaps prioritizing market-based equity at home but not beyond U.S.
borders. In the case of an arms control agreement, equality increases support for a
proposal that would limit nuclear arsenals while equity is unrelated to arms control
preferences, mirroring the pattern we observed for 3 of the 4 burden sharing items.
Second, these results underscore our argument that fairness is not inherently
prosocial: equity values discourage international economic agreements, for exam-
ple. Moreover, we find evidence that concerns about equality can increase demands
for military spending. Focused on outcomes, equality-minded respondents see prom-
ise in bolstering the U.S. defense budget if it might help solve international prob-
lems. Defense spending could therefore draw support from a coalition of militant
internationalists and the equality-minded Americans who otherwise eschew hawkish
politics (Maxey 2020).
Third, although research on foreign policy attitudes tends to divorce security from
economics and assume that international trade attitudes follow a different logic than
other foreign policy domains, we find evidence that equity and equality can shape
Powers et al. 19
236 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
public support for NATO and NAFTA alike. This finding complements a growing
body of work on the relationship between values and public opinion about interna-
tional economic policies (Kaltenthaler and Miller 2013; Rathbun 2016; Rathbun,
Powers, and Anders 2019).
Fourth, it illustrates the import ance of studying core values in foreign policy
preferences more generally: even though these foreign policy proposals are arguably
further removed from fairness considerations than the burden sharing vignettes are, a
set of Wald tests find that we experience a significant reduction in model fit when we
drop equity and equality from the two models where we have the strongest theore-
tical expectations (Free Trade and Military Spending), even when controlling for a
wide range of other demographic characteristics and foreign policy orientations.
Indeed, Online Appendix §2.5 shows that the effects of fairness hold when control-
ling for party identification and ideology in turn, despite the important role played by
partisanship in shaping policy preferences. Understanding respondents’ differential
concerns about each face of fairness thus systematically enhances our understanding
of their foreign policy preferences.
Fifth, the proposals that we focus on here each represent policy areas that have
been characterized by pronounced gender gaps: in the United States, women have
historically been less supportive of free trade (Mansfield, Mutz, and Silver 2015;
Guisinger 2016), more supportive of arms control (Silverman and Kumka 1987), and
less supportive of defense spending (Eichenberg and Stoll 2012) than men. Despite
extensive documentation of gender gaps in foreign policy public opinion, “the
reason for these differences remains elusive” (Lizotte 2019, 126). Given the
Arms Control Free Trade Military Spending
-0.5 0.0 0.5 -0.5 0.0 0.5 -0.5 0.0 0.5
Iso
CI
MI
Equity
Equality
Effect size
Figure 2. Equity, equality, and policy proposals. Note: N ¼ 489, 515, 477, respectively. Figures
display OLS coefficient estimates and 95 percent confidence intervals for equality, equity,
militant internationalism (MI), cooperative internationalism (CI) and isolationism from models
that also include additional demographic controls. To facilitate direct comparability, each
variable has been rescaled to range from 0 to 1, and higher values on the DV indicate support
for the policy.
20 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 237
apparent gender differences in fairness commitments, variation in concerns about
equality could be one explanation for these gaps.
Results from the OLS models, presented in Online Appendix §2.4, reveal no
effect of gender on support for the three policy proposals. Our interest does not lie
in the total effect, however, but in whether gender has any indirect effects through
values.
18
We thus estimate a series of nonparametric causal mediation models, in
which the effect of gender on each of these foreign policy issues is mediated by
concerns about each type of fairness, while controlling for a host of demographic
characteristics. Although care should be taken in interpreting these results given
potential confounders, the results suggest that fairness concerns offer one potential
explanation for gender differences in two of the three issues: arms control, and trade
attitudes.
The average causa l mediation effect (ACME) of gender on support for arms
control, through equality, is 0.007 (0.017, 0.00). To the extent that men are less
committed to equality than women, they will in turn be less supportive of arms
control. The ACME is small, but statistically significant. We find similar evidence
for indirect-only mediation on support for free trade. The effect of gender channeled
through equality is significant and negative, accounting for approximately 31.5 per-
cent of the total effect. These results suggest that the gender gap in trade attitudes
may be explained in part through women’s greater commitment to egalitarian out-
comes. We find no evidence that the relationship between gender and support for
these three policy issues is mediated by equity. Importantly, the absence of signif-
icant direct or total effects for gender implies one or more possible suppressors—
other, unmeasured mechanisms that push men toward arms control and free trade
(Rucker et al. 2011). Future research should account for equality values alongside
other relevant factors like partisanship, identity, and other prosocial values to offer a
more complete understanding of gender gaps in foreign policy attitudes.
Conclusion
In this article, we sought to contribute to the study of fairness in IR by reminding IR
scholars that fairness is multidimensional (Adams 1965; Deutsch 1975; Hochschild
1981). Whereas the existing literature on fairness in IR has focused almost exclusively
on fairness as equality, we can also understand fairness as equity. Because personal
values spill over into the foreign policy domain (Rathbun et al. 2016), both faces of
fairness are important for understanding the contours of foreign policy preferences.
Although IR scholars typically associate fairness with cooperation, our results
demonstrate that equity values encourage opposition to security cooperation and
public goods provision across several contexts, due in particular to concerns about
inadequate burden sharing. We therefore find evidence of a new psychological
microfoundation for isolationism, something existing sch olarship has failed to
uncover (Kertzer et al. 2014). Moreover, we fielded o ur survey in 2 014, before
Donald Trump campaigned on inequities in the US alliance system, which suggests
Powers et al. 21
238 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
that our findings are not merely an artifact of partisan cue-taking. Our results offer
further support for the continued importance of core values and moral judgments in
shaping foreign policy preferences (Bayram 2015; Rathbun et al. 2016; Kreps and
Maxey 2018), and in studying fairness concerns as a variable rather than a constant.
And although our findings are consistent with bottom-up theories of public opinion
in foreign policy (Kertzer and Zeitzoff 2017), they also suggest important implica-
tions for theories of elite political behavior. Framing research in American politics
argues that political elites seek to mobilize and persuade voters using appeals that
frame issues in terms of the values that resonate with their audience (Nelson, Claw-
son, and Oxley 1997). The fact that Republicans and Democrats alike value equity
suggest that it should be a particularly potent way to frame foreign policy issues.
We also observe important differences in how Republicans and Democrats think
about equality. Our findings thus contribute to a growing literature on partisanship
and ideology in foreign policy. IR scholars have found that Republicans and Dem-
ocrats tend to conduct systematically different types of foreign policies, not just
because each party’s base has a different set of interests, but because “right parties
have somewhat different values from left parties.” (Palmer, London, and Regan
2004, 1-24; see also Rathbun 2004; Bertoli, Dafoe, and Trager 2019). We observe
differences in how Democrats and Republicans conceptualize fairness—Democrats
place greater value on equality than Republicans do—that suggest a potential micro-
foundation for distinct partisan approaches to foreign policy.
Our findings also relate to research on partisan or ideological differences in moral
reasoning generally (Graham, Haidt, and Nosek 2009). Indeed, although our analysis
focused on the two faces of fairness in foreign policy, it also informs research on
public opinion about domestic issues—since the equity and equality scales can be
fruitfully applied in other contexts. As Hochschild (1981) noted nearly four decades
ago, many key debates in American political life involve competing conceptions of
fairness. Understanding individual differences in equity- and equality-based moral
judgments can therefore enrich our understanding of public opinion more broadly.
Acknowledgment
We thank Scott Clifford, Jeff Friedman, Chris Gelpi, Ravi Iyer, Rose McDermott, Chris Ray,
Julie Rose, Drew Rosenberg, and audiences at the 2017 ISA meeting and 2020 Grand Strategy
Conference at Ohio State’s Mershon Center for helpful feedback and discussions, and Chelsea
Lim and Felicia Jia for excellent research assistance.
Declaration of Conflicting Interests
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, author-
ship, and/or publication of this article.
Funding
The author(s) received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of
this article.
22 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 239
ORCID iD
Joshua D. Kertzer https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7358-0638
Supplemental Material
Supplemental material for this article is available online.
Notes
1. Barack Obama, quoted in Jeffrey Goldberg, April 2016, “The Obama Doctrine,” The
Atlantic.
2. Donald J. Trump. Twitter Post. July 9, 2018. 7:55 a.m. https://twitter.com/realDonald
Trump/status/1016289620596789248
3. Donald J. Trump, “President Donald J. Trump is Confronting China’s Unfair Trade
Policies,” The White House.
4. We use inequality to describe circumstances where group members receive dispara te
benefits, irrespective of contributions. “Inequity” exists when resource allocations are
not proportionate to relative contributions from beneficiaries. This distinction highlights
one potential source of confusion that arises from importing behavioral economics to IR:
scholars sometimes use “inequity aversion” to describe concerns about both inequity and
inequality, and test economic models of inequity aversion by assessing how participants
“respond to inequalities” (Wilson 2011, 208). The standard structure of laboratory eco-
nomic games contributes to this issue. A participant playing an ultimatum game often
lacks information about whether she or her partner has contributed more to the resource
endowment. Without a metric to determine the equitable input/outcome ratio, “the equi-
table outcome, is given by the egalitarian outcome” (Fehr and Schmidt 1999, 822).
Incorporating e arned endowments into lab experiments decreases the share of 50 -50
splits, suggesting that many games overestimate the prevalence of inequality aversion.
We avoid this complication by only using the terms equity and inequity in contexts where
relative contributions are known and relevant.
5. As Fiske and Tetlock (1997, 276), note, each face of fairness stems from a different
“relational model”: Equality constitutes fairness in Equality Matching relationships,
which are predicated on in-kind reciprocity and common among peers or co-workers.
Fairness as equity marks Market Pricing relations, where people interact according to a
principle of proportionality. See also Powers (2022) for a discussion of relational models
in IR.
6. Although equity concerns can draw on objective metrics—an investor will earn part of
the company’s profits in proportion to what she invests—subjective perceptions often
shape judgments (e.g., Trump 2020).
7. In addition to work on inequity aversion, which we describe below, the only other work
on equity in IR we are aware of is Gottfried and Trager (2016), which draws on equity
theory when presenting its theoretical model. Consistent with much of the behavioral
economic tradition more generally (see, e.g., Fehr and Schmidt 1999), however, it uses an
experimental protocol in which neither party has an unambiguous claim to a larger share
Powers et al. 23
240 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
of the disputed object (Gottfried and Trager 2016, 253). It therefore cannot distinguish
between effects from concerns about equity versus equality.
8. Although people who conceive of justice in terms of equality are more likely to endorse
separate other-regarding moral beliefs (Graham, Haidt, and Nosek 2009), equality is not a
proxy for general prosociality. Research from the moral foundations tradition shows that
the fairness and harm/care foundations co-vary—but they remain empirically and con-
ceptually distinct moral systems (Haidt 2012). Equality, like equity, taps beliefs about
justice (Meindl, Iyer, and Graham 2019), whereas harm/care refers to individuals’ con-
cerns about others’ suffering. Caring taps compassion, not fairness.
9. The sample closely matches the U.S. population on key variables including sex, age, race,
and region. Highly educated Americans are slightly over-represented in our sample. In
the Online Appendix, we show that our substantive conclusions hold when we reweight
the data to more closely match population parameters for educational attainment.
10. See Online Appendix §1.3 for a broader discussion of scale construction.
11. Moreover, the first and second factors have eigenvalues of 2.75 and 0.77, whereas the
third factor drops to 0.11.
12. Both are rescaled from 0 to 1 in the analysis below for ease of interpretability.
13. Importantly, these differences in equity are ideological rather than partisan—Republicans
do not value equity significantly more than Democrats do (t ¼ 1:56, p < 0:112).
14. George W. Bush, 2000. “October 11, 2000 Debate Transcript.” Transcript available at
https://www.debates.org/voter-education/debate-transcripts/october-11-2000-debate-
transcript/.
15. Only a random subsample of partic ipants were administe red these policy proposals,
which restricts the sample size but otherwise does not affect the analyses in this section.
16. Indeed, Mutz and Kim (2017, 842) find that holding gains for the U.S. constant, people
with low social dominance orientation—who value group equality—report greater sup-
port for trade agreements that present a win-win situation, where the U.S. trading partner
also gains jobs from the agreement.
17. See Online Appendix §2.5 for the results in tabular form, which also suggest we should
not be concerned about post-treatment bias, in that our results hold without these covari-
ates as well.
18. Zhao, Lynch Jr, and Chen (2010, 199) contend that it is not necessary to observe
“a significant zero-order effect of X on Y ...to establish mediation.” Rucker et al.
(2011, 361-62) similarly “question the requirement that a total X ! Y effect be present
before assessing mediation.” They summarize that “the lack of an effect ...does not
preclude the possibility of observing indirect effects.” We therefore rely on the theore-
tical foundations provided in literature on gender gaps to probe indirect-only mediation
despite the absence of a total effect (Rucker et al. 2011, 368).
References
Adams, J. Stacy. 1965. “Inequity in Soc ial Exchange.” Advances in Experimental Social
Psychology 2:267-99.
24 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 241
Albin, Cecilia, and Daniel Druckman. 2012. “Equality Matters: Negotiating an End to Civil
Wars.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 56 (2): 155-82.
Baldwin , David Allen. 1993. Neorealism and Neolibe ralism: The Contemporary Debate.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Baum, Matthew A., and Philip B. K. Potter. 2015. War and Democratic Constraint: How the
Public Influences Foreign Policy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bayram, A. Burcu. 2015. “What Drives Modern Diogenes? Individual Values and Cosmo-
politan Allegiance.” European Journal of International Relations 21 (2): 451-79.
Bechtel, Michael M., Jens Hainmueller, and Yotam Margalit. 2017. “Policy Design and
Domestic Support for International Bailouts.” European Journal of Political Research
56 (4): 864-86.
Berinsky, Adam J. 2009. In Time of War: Understanding American Public Opinion from
World War II to Iraq. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Bernauer, Thomas, Robert Gampfer, and Aya Kachi. 2014. “European Unilateralism and
Involuntary Burd en-sharing in Global Climate Politics: A Pub lic Opinion Perspe ctive
from the Other Side.” European Union Politics 15 (1): 132-51.
Bertoli, Andrew, Allan Dafoe, and Robert F. Trager. 2019. “Is There a War Party? Party
Change, the Left–Right Divide, and International Conflict.” Journal of Conflict Resolution
63 (4): 950-75.
Brooks, Deborah Jordan, and Benjamin A. Valentino. 2011. “A War of One’s Own: Under-
standing the Gender Gap in Support for War.” Public Opinion Quarterly 75 (2): 270-86.
Brooks, Stephen G., and William C. Wohlforth. 2016. America Abroad: Why the Sole
Superpower Should Not Pull Back from the World. New York: Oxford University Press.
Brutger, Ryan, and Brian Rathbun. 2020. “Fair Share? Equality and Equity in American
Attitudes toward Trade.” International Organization 75 (3): 880-900.
Camerer, Colin F. 1997. “Progress in Behavioral Game Theory.” Journal of Economic
Perspectives 11 (4): 167-88.
Chilton, Adam S., Helen V. Milner, and Dustin Tingley. 2020. “Reciprocity and Public Oppo-
sition to Foreign Direct Investment. British Journal of Political Science 50 (1): 129-53.
Chittick, William O., Keith R. Billingsley, and Rick Travis. 1995. “A Three-dimensional
Model of American Foreign Policy Beliefs.” Inte rnational Studies Quarterly 39 (3):
313-31.
Chu, Jonathan A. 2019. “A Clash of Norms? How Reciprocity and International Humanitarian
Law affect American Opinion on the Treatment of POWs.” Journal of Conflict Resolution
63 (5): 1140-64.
Clifford, Scott, Vijeth Iyengar, Roberto Cabeza, and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. 2015. “Moral
Foundations Vignettes: A Standardized Stimulus Database of Scenarios based on Moral
Foundations Theory.” Behavior Research Methods 47 (4): 1178-98.
Cohrs, J. Christopher, Barbara Moschner, Jurgen Maes, and Sven Kielmann. 2005. “Personal
Values and Attitudes toward War.” Peace and Conflict 11 (3): 293-312.
Cram, Laura, Adam Moore, Victor Olivieri, and Felix Suessenbach. 2018. “Fair Is Fair, or Is It?
Territorial Identity Triggers Influence Ultimatum Game Behavior. Political Psychology
39 (6): 1233-50.
Powers et al. 25
242 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
DeScioli, Peter, Maxim Massenkoff, Alex Shaw, Michael Bang Petersen, and Robert
Kurzban. 2014. Equity or Equality? Moral Judgments Follow the Money.”
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 281: 20142112.
Deutsch, Morton. 1975. “Equity, Equality, and Need: What Determines Which Value Will Be
Used as the Basis of Distributive Justice?” Journal of Social Issues 31 (3): 137-49.
DeVoe, Sanford E., and Sheena S. Iyengar. 2010. “Medium of Exchange Matters: What’s Fair
for Goods Is Unfair for Money.” Psychological Science 21 (2): 159-62.
Efrat, Asif, and Abraham L. Newman. 2016. Deciding to Defer: The Importance of Fairness in
Resolving Transnational Jurisdictional Conflicts.” International Organization 70 (02): 409-41.
Eichenberg, Richard C., and Richard J. Stoll. 2012. “Gender Difference or Parallel Publics?
The Dynamics of Defense Spending Opinions in the United States, 1965–2007.” Journal
of Conflict Resolution 56 (2): 331-48.
Fehr, Ernst, Helen Bernhard, and Bettina Rockenbach. 2008. “Egalitarianism in Young Chil-
dren.” Nature 454: 1079-83.
Fehr, Ernst, and Klaus M. Schmidt. 1999. “A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Coop-
eration.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 114 (3): 817-68.
Feldman, Stanley, and John Zaller. 1992. “The Political Culture of Ambivalence: Ideological
Responses to the Welfare State.” American Journal of Political Science 36: 268-307.
Fiske, Alan Page, and Philip E. Tetlock. 1997. “Taboo Trade-offs: Reactions to Transactions
that Transgress the Spheres of Justice.” Political Psychology 18 (2): 255-97.
Fuhrmann, Matthew. 2020. “When Do Leaders Free-ride? Business Experience and Contri-
butions to Collective Defense.” American Journal of Political Science 64 (2): 416-31.
Goddard, Stacie E. 2006. “Uncommon Ground: Indivisible Territor y and the Politics of
Legitimacy.” International Organization 60 (1): 35-68.
Goren, Paul, Harald Schoen, Jason Reifler, Thomas Scotto, and William Chittick. 2016. “A
Unified Theory of Value-based Reasoning and US Public Opinion.” Political Behavior 38
(4): 977-97.
Gottfried, Matthew S., and Robert F. Trager. 2016. “A Preference for War: How Fairness and
Rhetoric Influence Leadership Incentives in Crises.” International Studies Quarterly 60
(2): 243-57.
Graham, Jesse, Jonathan Haidt, and Brian A. Nosek. 2009. “Liberals and Conservatives Rely
on Different Sets of Moral Foundations.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
96 (5): 1029-46.
Gravelle, Timothy B., Jason Reifler, and Thomas J. Scotto. 2017. “The Structure of Foreign
Policy Attitudes in Transatlantic Perspective: Comparing the United States, United King-
dom, France and Germany.” European Journal of Political Research 56 (4): 757-76.
Grieco, Joseph M. 1988. “Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the
Newest Liberal Institutionalism.” International Organization 42 (3): 485-507.
Guisinger, Alexandra. 2016. “Information, Gender, and Differences in Individual Preferences
for Trade.” Journal of Women, Politics & Policy 37 (4): 538-61.
Guisinger, Alexandra, and Elizabeth N. Saunders. 2017. “Mapping the Boundaries of Elite
Cues: How Elites Shape Mass Opinion Across International Issues.” International Studies
Quarterly 61 (2): 425-41.
26 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 243
Gu
¨
th, Werner, Rolf Schmittberger, and Bernd Schwarze. 1982. “An Experimental Analysis of
Ultimatum Bargaining.” Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 3 (4): 367-88.
Haidt, Jonathan. 2012. The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and
Religion. New York: Pantheon Books.
Haidt, Jonatha n. 20 13. “Of Freedom and Fairness. Democracy: A Journal of Ideas 28.
Accessed August 16, 2021.https://democracyjournal.org/magazine/28/of-freedom-and-
fairness/
Hochschild, Jennifer L. 1981. What’s Fair?: American Beliefs about Distributive Justice.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hurwitz, Jon, and Mark Peffley. 1987. “How Are Foreign Policy At titudes Structured?
A Hierarchical Model.” The American Political Science Review 81:1099-120.
Iyer, Ravi. 2010. “Democrats and Republicans Agree that Justice and Fairness Are about
Equity, Not Equality or Impartiality.” Accessed August 16, 2021. https://www.yourmor
als.org/blog/2010/02/democrats-and-republicans-agree-that-justice-fairness-are-about-
equity-not-equality-or-impartiality/
Jennings, M. Kent. 1991. “Thinking about Social Injustice.” Political Psychology 12 (2):
187-204.
Jost, John T., Christopher M. Federico, and Jaime L. Napier. 2009. “Political Ideology:
Its Structure, Functions, and Elective Affinities.” Annual Review of Psychology 60:
307-37.
Kaltenthaler, Karl, and William J. Miller. 2013. “Social Psychology and Public Support for
Trade Liberalization.” International Studies Quarterly 57 (4): 784-90.
Kapstein, Ethan B. 2008. “Fairness Considerations in World Politics: Lessons from Interna-
tional Trade Negotiations.” Political Science Quarterly 123 (2): 229-45.
Kertzer, Joshua D., Kathleen E. Powers, Brian C. Rathbun, and Ravi Iyer. 2014. “Do Moral
Values Shape Foreign Policy Preferences?” Journal of Politics 76 (3): 825-40.
Kertzer, Joshua D., and Brian C. Rathbun. 2015. “Fair Is Fair: Social Preferences and Reci-
procity in International Politics.” World Politics 67 (04): 613-55.
Kertzer, Joshua D., and Thomas Zeitzoff. 2017. “A Bottom-up Theory of Public Opinion
about Foreign Policy.” American Journal of Political Science 61 (3): 543-58.
Kreps, Sarah, and Sarah Maxey. 2018. “Mechanisms of Morality: Sources of Support for
Humanitarian Intervention.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 62 (8): 1814-42.
Liberman, Peter. 2006. “An Eye for an Eye: Public Support for War again st Evildoers.”
International Organization 60 (3): 687.
Lizotte, Mary-Kate. 2019. “Investigating the Origins of the Gender Gap in Support for War.”
Political Studies Review 17 (6): 124-35.
Lu
¨
, Xiaobo, Kenneth Scheve, and Matthew J. Slaughter. 2012. “Inequity Aversion and the
International Distribution of Trade Protection.” American Journal of Political Science
56 (3): 638-54.
Mansfield, Edward D., Diana C. Mutz, and Laura R. Silver. 2015. “Men, Women, Trade, and
Free Markets.” International Studies Quarterly 59 (2): 303-15.
Maxey, Sarah. 2020. “The Power of Humanitarian Narratives: A Domestic Coalition Theory
of Justifications for Military Action.” Political Research Quarterly 73 (3): 680-95.
Powers et al. 27
244 Journal of Conflict Resolution 66(2)
Meegan, Dan. 2019. America the Fair: Using Brain Science to Create a More Just Nation.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Meindl, Peter, Ravi Iyer, and Jesse Graham. 2019. “Distributive Justice Beliefs Are Guided by
Whether People Think the Ultimate Goal of Society is Well-being or Power.” Basic and
Applied Social Psychology 41 (6): 359-85.
Mutz, Diana C., and Eunji Kim. 2017. “The Impact of In-group Favoritism on Trade Pre-
ferences.” International Organization 71 (4): 827-50.
Nelson, Thomas E., Rosalee A. Clawson, and Zoe M. Oxley. 1997. “Media Framing of a Civil
Liberties Conflict and Its Effect on Tolerance.” American Political Science Review 91 (3):
567-83.
Oneal, John R. 1990. “The Theory of Collective Action and Burden Sharing in NATO.”
International Organization 44 (3): 379-402.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1998. “A Behavioral Approach to the Rational Choice Theory of Collective
Action: Presidential Address, American Political Science Association, 1997.” American
Political Science Review 92 (1): 1-22.
Palmer, Glenn, Tamar R. London, and Patrick M. Regan. 2004. “What’s Stopping You?: The
Sources of Political Constraints on International Conflict Behavior in Parliamentary
Democracies.” International Interactions 30 (1): 1-24.
Powers, Kathleen E. 2022. Nationalisms in International Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Rai, Tage Shakti, and Alan Page Fiske. 2011. “Moral Psychology Is Relationship Regulation:
Moral Motives for Unity, Hierarchy, Equality, and Proportionality.” Psychological Review
118 (1): 57.
Rasinski, Kenneth A. 1987. “What’s Fair Is Fair—Or Is It? Value Differences Underlying
Public Views about Social Justice.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53 (1):
201.
Rathbun, Brian C. 2004. Partisan Interventions: European Party Politics and Peace
Enforcement in the Balkans. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Rathbun, Brian C. 2016. “Wedges and Widgets: Liberalism, Libertarianism, and the Trade
Attitudes of the American Mass Public and Elites.” Foreign Policy Analysis 12 (1):
85-108.
Rathbun, Brian C., Joshua D. Kertzer, Jason Reifler, Paul Goren, and Thomas J. Scotto. 2016.
“Taking Foreign Policy Personally: Personal Values and Foreign Policy Attitudes.”
International Studies Quarterly 60 (1): 124-37.
Rathbun, Brian C., Kathleen E. Powers, and Therese Anders. 2019. “Moral Hazard: German
Public Opinion on the Greek Debt Crisis.” Political Psychology 40 (3): 523-41.
Rathbun, Brian C., and Rachel Stein. 2020. “Greater Goods: Morality and Attitudes toward
the Use of Nuclear Weapons.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 64 (5): 787-816.
Rucker, Derek D., Kristopher J. Preacher, Zakary L. Tormala, and Richard E. Petty. 2011.
“Mediation Analysis in Social Psychology: Current Practices and New Recommendations.
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 5 (6): 359-71.
Sagan, Scott Douglas. 1995. The Limits of Safety: Organizations, Accidents, and Nuclear
Weapons. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
28 Journal of Conflict Resolution XX(X)
Powers et al. 245
Scott, John T., Richard E. Matland, Philip A. Michelbach, and Brian H. Bornstein. 2001. “Just
Deserts: An Experimental Study of Distributive Justice Norms.” American Journal of
Political Science 45:749-67.
Silverman, Jane M., and Donald S. Kumka. 1987. “Gender Differences in Attitudes toward
Nuclear War and Disarmament.” Sex Roles 16 (3-4): 189-203.
Starmans, Christina, Mark Sheskin, and Paul Bloom. 2017. “Why People Prefer Unequal
Societies.” Nature Human Behaviour 1 (4): 1-7.
Thaler, Richard H. 1988. “Anomalies: The Ultimatum Game.” Journal of Economic
Perspectives 2 (4): 195-206.
Trump, Kris-Stella. 2018. “Income Inequality Influences Perceptions of Legitimate Income
Differences.” British Journal of Political Science 48 (4): 929-52.
Trump, Kris-Stella. 2020. “When and Why Is Economic Inequality Seen as Fair.” Current
Opinion in Behavioral Sciences 34: 46-51.
Wilson, Rick K. 2011. “The Contribution of Behavioral Economics to Political Science.”
Annual Review of Political Science 14: 201-23.
Wittkopf, Eugene R. 1990. Faces of Internationalism: Public Opinion and American Foreign
Policy. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Zhao, Xinshu, John G. Lynch Jr, and Qimei Chen. 2010. “Reconsidering Baron and Kenny:
Myths an d Truths a bout Mediation Analysis.” Journal of Consumer Research 37 (2):
197-206.
Powers et al. 29