689
PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY:
THE HISTORICAL PROTECTION OF PATENTS UNDER
THE TAKINGS CLAUSE
ADAM MOSSOFF
INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 690
I. M
ODERN MYOPIA: NO PATENTS UNDER THE TAKINGS CLAUSE......... 693
II. T
HE HISTORY OF PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE
PROPERTY............................................................................................ 700
III. P
ATENTS, PROPERTY, AND CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY
P
AST AND PRESENT ............................................................................. 711
C
ONCLUSION................................................................................................... 724
Conventional wisdom maintains that early courts never protected patents as
constitutional private property under the Takings Clause. In examining long-
forgotten judicial opinions and legislative records, this Article reveals that this
is a profoundly mistaken historical claim. Nineteenth-century courts, securing
to inventors the fruits of their labors, enthusiastically applied the Takings
Clause to patents, and Congress explicitly codified this jurisprudence in the
early twentieth century. It is perplexing that this historical development in
both constitutional law and patent law has become obscured to modern courts
and scholars. This Article thus concludes with a possible answer to this
conundrum, drawing upon the intellectual history of property theory:
Ultimately, the eclipse of the nineteenth-century patent takings jurisprudence
may be an unintended consequence of the legal realists’ radical
transformation of property theory at the turn of the last century.
This intellectual history is important because it exposes the pervasive
misunderstanding of the history concerning two significant constitutional
provisions – the Takings Clause and the Copyright and Patent Clause. Courts
Associate Professor of Law, Michigan State University College of Law. J.D.,
University of Chicago; M.A., Columbia University; B.A., University of Michigan. I am
grateful to William Baude, Thomas Bowden, Eric R. Claeys, Thomas F. Cotter, Brett
Frischmann, Philip Hamburger, Paul J. Heald, Brian Kalt, Roberta R. Kwall, Mark Lemley,
Henry E. Smith, and Eugene Volokh for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts. This
Article evolved from a long-term research project on the intellectual history of American
patent law, and this portion of the project benefited from comments received at a workshop
at the George Washington University School of Law, as well as at the American Society for
Legal History Annual Meeting and the Intellectual Property Scholars Conference at DePaul
University College of Law. The Law Library at the Michigan State University College of
Law provided invaluable research assistance.
690 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
and scholars can no longer rely on the conventional wisdom to conclude that
patents are not protected under the Takings Clause, or that this issue is novel
and uncertain. Doctrinally, this Article also uncovers a venerable
jurisprudence grappling with the constitutional limits on what jurists used to
refer to as the unauthorized “pirating” of patented inventions by government
officials. In a regulatory takings case, in particular, such long-standing
doctrine is highly relevant in defining the scope of the constitutional security
afforded to a property right today. As patented drugs and other inventions are
increasingly the subject of regulations, this Article establishes that the
constitutional and policy issues inherent in these governmental actions are not
new. Courts have long embraced patents as constitutional private property.
INTRODUCTION
Patents are property. The question that haunts scholars and courts today is
whether patents also are constitutional private property, falling within the
ambit of protections afforded to “private propertyunder the Takings Clause.
1
Modern takings and intellectual property scholarship concludes that this
question is novel, and its answer uncertain.
2
Courts agree that the issue is
ambiguous, at best. As recently as March 2006, the Court of Appeals for the
Federal Circuit held that patents are not secured under the Takings Clause.
3
Several years earlier, though, the U.S. Supreme Court seemed to suggest
otherwise.
4
Regardless of whether courts and scholars believe the Takings
Clause should apply to patents as a normative matter, they are unanimous in
their view of the constitutional history: no nineteenth-century court held that
the Takings Clause applies to patents.
1
U.S. CONST. amend. V (“[N]or shall private property be taken for public use, without
just compensation.”).
2
See, e.g., DAVID A. DANA & THOMAS W. MERRILL, PROPERTY: TAKINGS 233 (2002)
(stating that “[t]he application of the Takings Clause to intellectual property trademarks,
copyrights and patents has not yet been seriously tested in the courts”); Thomas F. Cotter,
Do Federal Uses of Intellectual Property Implicate the Fifth Amendment?, 50 FLA. L. REV.
529, 529 (1998) (positing that “the law of takings with regard to
intellectual property can
only be characterized as a muddle”); Shubha Ghosh,
Toward a Theory of Regulatory
Takings for Intellectual Property: The Path Left Open After
College Savings v. Florida
Prepaid, 37 S
AN DIEGO L. REV. 637, 667 (2000) (claiming that applying the Takings Clause
to “intellectual property or intangible property would occur only through analogy”).
3
See Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 442 F.3d 1345 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (per curiam),
rehearing en banc denied, 464 F.3d 1335 (Fed. Cir. 2006). In a separate case, the Court of
Federal Claims came to a similar conclusion eight years earlier.
See De Graffenried v.
United States, 29 Fed. Cl. 384 (1998) (holding that patents are not secured under the
Takings Clause).
4
Festo Corp. v. Shoketsu Kinzoku Kogyo Kabushiki Co., 535 U.S. 722, 739 (2002)
(invoking standard from the regulatory takings doctrine that patent rights constitute “the
legitimate expectations of inventors in their property”).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 691
This historical claim is profoundly mistaken. In three parts, this Article will
uncover long-forgotten nineteenth-century jurisprudence in the Supreme Court
and in lower federal courts, showing that jurists once enthusiastically held that
patents were protected under the Takings Clause. First, this Article will survey
the views of modern courts and scholars, who seem to agree in a rare case of
unanimity that the historical record reflects no instance of a federal court
holding that the Takings Clause applies to patents. For many intellectual
property scholars, in particular, this historical claim is important, as it forms an
important basis of their critiques of modern, expansive patent practices.
5
Second, this Article will identify the logical progression in nineteenth-century
constitutional jurisprudence leading to the famous 1878
McKeever’s Case,
6
which held that patents were secured under the Takings Clause. The
juxtaposition of these historical facts and the modern misunderstanding of
them raises an intriguing question: Why are courts and scholars today so
mistaken about the historical protection of patents as constitutional private
property? This Article concludes with some observations on how this
conundrum arose, suggesting that it may be an unintended consequence of the
legal realists’ radical transformation of property theory at the turn of the last
century.
This intellectual history reveals that modern courts and scholars have
overlooked significant constitutional jurisprudence given fundamental
differences in how courts and scholars have conceptualized both property and
patent rights. At the turn of the twentieth century, the legal realists rejected the
natural rights conception of property as securing the exclusive rights to
acquire, use, and dispose of one’s possessions, which was the leading property
theory in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
7
The realists redefined
property as securing principally the right to exclude, which is the dominant
conception of property today.
8
This radical transformation in property theory
necessarily affected how courts and scholars conceptualized other types of
property, such as the intangible property in a patent, which is also now defined
as securing only the right to exclude.
9
This, in turn, impacted how modern
courts and scholars have understood how patents rights were defined and
secured in the nineteenth century, when property rights were more broadly
conceived as securing exclusive use rights.
10
It is important to bear in mind the scope of my thesis. This Article builds on
my earlier work, in which I discuss the evolution of patent rights at common
5
See infra notes 47-51 and accompanying text.
6
McKeever v. United States (McKeever’s Case), 14 Ct. Cl. 396 (1878).
7
See discussion infra Part III.
8
See infra notes 139-43 and accompanying text.
9
See infra notes 144-47 and accompanying text.
10
See infra notes 150-62 and accompanying text.
692 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
law and in the early American Republic,
11
but here I explain only the historical
protection of patents as constitutional private property. Takings scholars
should find this Article relevant to how they have framed their analyses of
takings doctrine – they have missed much of the early constitutional protection
of
intangible property
12
– but this Article does not seek to resolve their debates
concerning the historical application of the Takings Clause as such.
13
Furthermore, the normative question of whether patents
should be secured as
property rights, or whether patents
should be secured as private property under
the Takings Clause, cannot be answered by history alone,
14
and in any case
could not be addressed sufficiently in a brief Article.
Yet the evidence presented here is not a mere historical or academic
curiosity. This Article establishes that modern courts and scholars have been
relying on incorrect historical claims to justify their decisions and policy
prescriptions. This is significant because patented drugs and other inventions
are increasingly the subject of regulations, and thus the constitutional security
in these legal entitlements is a particularly salient issue in our public policy
debates. Following September 11, 2001, for instance, the federal government
11
See generally Adam Mossoff, Rethinking the Development of Patents: An Intellectual
History, 1550-1800
, 52 HASTINGS L.J. 1255 (2001) [hereinafter Mossoff, Rethinking the
Development of Patents
]; Adam Mossoff, Who Cares What Thomas Jefferson Thought
About Patents? Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege” in Historical Context
, 92 CORNELL L.
R
EV. 953 (2007) [hereinafter Mossoff, Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege”].
12
Since takings scholars focus almost exclusively on land, this Article exposes a
substantial gap in their scholarship.
See, e.g., John F. Hart, Land Use Law in the Early
Republic and the Original Meaning of the Takings Clause
, 94 NW. U. L. REV. 1099 (2000);
Carol M. Rose, Mahon
Reconstructed: Why the Takings Issue Is Still a Muddle, 57 S. CAL.
L. R
EV. 561 (1984); Jed Rubenfeld, Usings, 102 YALE L.J. 1077, 1077-1110 (1993). In fact,
there is no discussion of patent takings in two prominent monographs on takings.
See
BRUCE A. ACKERMAN, PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE CONSTITUTION (1977); RICHARD A.
E
PSTEIN, TAKINGS: PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE POWER OF EMINENT DOMAIN (1985).
Professors Tom Merrill and David Dana do address takings of “intangible rights” in a brief
chapter in a recently published book, but they focus entirely on very recent case law. D
ANA
& MERRILL, supra note 2, at 228-53. Thus, takings scholars should find this Article relevant
insofar as it reveals that courts have long embraced
intangible property as falling within the
definition of “private property” secured under the Takings Clause.
See discussion infra
Part II.
13
Compare Eric R. Claeys, Takings, Regulations, and Natural Property Rights, 88
C
ORNELL L. REV. 1549 (2003) (claiming that early courts used natural rights theory to create
a pre-twentieth-century regulatory takings doctrine)
with William Michael Treanor, The
Original Understanding of the Takings Clause and the Political Process
, 95 COLUM. L.
R
EV. 782 (1995) (proposing that early courts provided almost no protection under state or
federal takings clauses to property that was negatively affected by governmental
regulations).
14
Cf. Georgia v. Randolph, 126 S. Ct. 1515, 1528 (2006) (Stevens, J., concurring)
(noting in a Fourth Amendment case that constitutional law history is “usually relevant but
not necessarily dispositive” in deciding cases today).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 693
threatened to suspend Bayer’s patent on Cipro in order to cheaply obtain vast
quantities of the antibiotic that best treats anthrax.
15
Given the status of patents
as property, these and other state actions raise questions concerning the
constitutional limitations imposed on the government vis-à-vis the patents it
grants to inventors.
16
In addressing these issues today, courts and scholars justify their
conclusions on the basis of mistaken historical authority, and this Article
establishes that this reliance is no longer defensible. There needs to be a fresh
review of the constitutional and policy issues implicated in a patent takings
case. In this respect, this Article is relevant to the continuing debates over the
nature of patent rights revealing a substantial nineteenth-century
jurisprudence applying the Takings Clause to patents that has become eclipsed
to modern courts and scholars.
I. M
ODERN MYOPIA: NO PATENTS UNDER THE TAKINGS CLAUSE
It is intriguing that modern courts and scholars believe that patents have
never been secured as constitutional private property. It is beyond cavil that
patents are property rights,
17
and currently there is a vibrant debate among
scholars and jurists as to whether the recent expansion in these property rights
is unprecedented, unjustified, or both.
18
Given this debate, one might expect
the relevant historical jurisprudence to be mined for its doctrinal or policy
analyses refuting or supporting the arguments proffered by the relevant players
today. Yet, despite this sharp policy divide, everyone believes that patents
were never secured as constitutional private property in the nineteenth century.
This history might be relevant if only because courts seem schizophrenic in
their decisions today. As a doctrinal matter, some courts suggest that patents
15
See Jill Carroll & Ron Winslow, Bayer Agrees To Slash Price for Cipro Drug, WALL
ST. J., Oct. 25, 2001, at A3 (“The agreement [between Bayer and the U.S. government]
comes after a high-stakes threat by Tommy Thompson, HHS secretary, to break Bayer’s
patent for Cipro if he didn’t get the price he wanted.”); Shankar Vedantam, Cipro Is Not the
Only Pill That Fights Anthrax
, WASH. POST, Oct. 17, 2001, at A20 (reporting that Senator
Charles E. Schumer “issued a public appeal that the government suspend Bayer’s patents
and allow generic companies to add to the supply”).
16
See, e.g., Fla. Prepaid Postsecondary Educ. Expense Bd. v. Coll. Sav. Bank, 527 U.S.
627, 642 (1999) (holding that patents are property interests secured under the Due Process
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment in a case involving a state’s unauthorized use of a
patented invention).
17
See, e.g., 35 U.S.C. § 261 (2000) (“[P]atents shall have the attributes of personal
property.”); Festo Corp. v. Shoketsu Kinzoku Kogyo Kabushiki Co., 535 U.S. 722, 730
(2002) (stating that a patent “is a property right”); Fla. Prepaid, 527 U.S. at 642
(“Patents . . . have long been considered a species of property.”); United States v. Dubilier
Condenser Corp., 289 U.S. 178, 186-87 (1933) (explaining that “a patent is not, accurately
speaking, a monopoly,” but rather “[a] patent is property”).
18
See infra notes 47-51 and accompanying text.
694 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
are entitled to protection under the Takings Clause and others disagree.
19
Complicating the issue, a federal statute (28 U.S.C. § 1498) mandates that the
government pay “reasonable and entire compensation” whenever “an
invention . . . covered by a patent of the United States is used or manufactured
by or for the United States.”
20
Since the early twentieth century, courts have
recognized this statutory requirement as executing the eminent domain power
of the federal government,
21
which tacitly acknowledges that patents are
property rights accorded constitutional protection under the Takings Clause.
Perhaps this was the reason why the Supreme Court held in 2002 in
Festo
Corp. v. Shoketsu Kinzoku Kogyo Kabushiki Co.
22
that patent rights constitute
“the legitimate expectations of inventors in their property.”
23
In saying this,
the
Festo Court applied to patents one of the contemporary standards securing
tangible property rights under the Takings Clause.
24
As further evidence that
the
Festo Court had takings doctrine on its mind, it warned the Federal Circuit
that it must neither “disrupt” nor “risk destroying” these “settled expectations”
in exercising its exclusive jurisdiction in deciding patent appeals.
25
Although
Festo was a patent infringement case, not a takings case, it seemed to establish
an important constitutional claim: patent rights represent “legitimate
19
Compare Festo Corp., 535 U.S. at 739 (explaining that patent rights constitute “the
legitimate expectations of inventors in their property,” invoking a standard from regulatory
takings doctrine) with Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 442 F.3d 1345, 1352 (Fed. Cir. 2006)
(per curiam) (rejecting claim that patents are secured under the Takings Clause),
rehearing
en banc denied
, 464 F.3d 1335 (Fed. Cir. 2006).
20
28 U.S.C. § 1498(a) (2000).
21
See, e.g., Crozier v. Fried. Krupp Aktiengesellschaft, 224 U.S. 290, 307 (1912)
(holding that a suit under the predecessor statute to § 1498(a) provides all the requirements
necessary to sustain the statute as an exercise of the federal government’s eminent domain
power); Decca Ltd. v. United States, 544 F.2d 1070, 1082 (Ct. Cl. 1976) (“It is [the
government’s] taking of a license, without compensation, that is, under an eminent domain
theory, the basis for a suit under § 1498.”); Carter-Wallace, Inc. v. United States, 449 F.2d
1374, 1390 (Ct. Cl. 1971) (Nichols, J., concurring) (assessing a claim under § 1498 as a
claim “to recover just compensation for a taking under the power of Eminent Domain”);
Irving Air Chute Co. v. United States, 93 F. Supp. 633, 635 (Ct. Cl. 1950) (“The
Government urges, rightly, that 28 U.S.C.A. § 1498, is in effect, an eminent domain statute,
which entitles the Government to manufacture or use a patented article becoming liable to
pay compensation to the owner of the patent.”).
22
535 U.S. 722 (2002).
23
Id. at 739.
24
See Penn Cent. Transp. Co. v. New York City, 438 U.S. 104, 124 (1978) (identifying
“investment-backed expectations” as a factor in assessing whether a government regulation
results in a compensable taking of property under the Takings Clause).
25
Festo Corp., 535 U.S. at 739.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 695
expectations” on par with property rights in land and chattels already secured
under the Takings Clause of the Constitution.
26
This conclusion, of course, is far too superficial and easy, and most agree
that the status of patents as constitutional private property is far from clear.
The Federal Circuit’s split decision in March 2006 in
Zoltek Corp. v. United
States
27
best illustrates the confusion on this issue. In Zoltek, the Federal
Circuit refused to apply the Takings Clause to patents, noting that “patent
rights are a creature of federal law.”
28
As such, patentees have only those
rights expressly provided by Congress, and § 1498, which mandates payment
to patentees following unauthorized uses by the government, revealed that
these statutory rights were not previously secured under the Constitution.
29
As
the court put it: “Had Congress intended to clarify the dimensions of the patent
rights as property interests under the Fifth Amendment, there would have been
no need for the new and limited sovereign immunity waiver” in § 1498.
30
26
This conclusion finds additional support in the Festo Court’s scolding of the Federal
Circuit for abrogating a long-standing patent infringement concept known as the doctrine of
equivalents. The Court concluded that the Federal Circuit “ignored the guidance of Warner-
Jenkinson
, which instructed that courts must be cautious before adopting changes that
disrupt the settled expectations of the inventing community.”
Id. Here, the Court was
referring to its holding in
Warner-Jenkinson Co. v. Hilton Davis Chem. Co., 520 U.S. 17
(1997), that nineteenth- and early twentieth-century infringement doctrines survived
Congress’s enactment of the 1952 Patent Act, ch. 950, 66 Stat. 792. See Warner-Jenkinson,
520 U.S. at 26. Thus,
Warner-Jenkinson and Festo established that the expectations
inherent in the patent since the nineteenth century are implicitly secured as constitutional
private property, although Congress is free to negate these expectations prospectively under
its plenary power to define the nature of the “exclusive Right” secured under Article I,
Section 8. See infra notes 59-63 and accompanying text (discussing McClurg v. Kingsland,
42 U.S. (1 How.) 202 (1843)).
27
442 F.3d 1345 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (per curiam), rehearing en banc denied, 464 F.3d 1335
(Fed. Cir. 2006).
28
Id. at 1352.
29
Zoltek raised a Fifth Amendment claim because part of the alleged infringement by the
government occurred in a foreign jurisdiction, and thus the government was immunized
from liability under § 1498(c). Id. at 1349.
30
Id. at 1352. In a concurring opinion, Judge Dyk reiterated this argument from the
majority
per curiam opinion in almost identical language, stating that “[p]atent rights are
creatures of federal statute,” and that the statutory framework of rights and remedies
provided to patentees precludes applying the Takings Clause to patents. See id. at 1370
(Dyk, J., concurring).
The canon prohibiting courts from construing statutes in a manner that makes them
superfluous militates in favor of this conclusion.
See 1A NORMAN J. SINGER, STATUTES AND
STATUTORY CONSTRUCTION § 25:2 (6th ed., 2002 rev.) (stating that “[n]o statute is intended
by the legislature to be wholly superfluous”);
see also Supervisor of Assessments v.
Southgate Harbor, 369 A.2d 1053, 1055 (Md. 1977) (recognizing as “a hornbook rule of
statutory construction” that “a statute is to be read so that no word, clause, sentence or
phrase shall be rendered surplusage, superfluous, meaningless, or nugatory”). However, the
696 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
Further highlighting the courts’ ambivalence on the patent takings issue,
Judge Plager dissented from the original panel decision in
Zoltek and Judge
Newman dissented from the Federal Circuit’s denial of Zoltek’s petition for en
banc review. Both Judge Plager and Judge Newman argued vociferously that
patents should be secured under the Takings Clause. They drew this
conclusion, in part, given the classification of patents as “property.”
31
Judge
Plager agreed, however, with the conventional wisdom that the question of
whether “an owner of a United States patent [may] bring a cause of action
under the Fifth Amendment to the Constitution against the United States for a
‘taking’ as all other owners of property rights may . . . has never been
addressed directly by this or any other court.”
32
And while Judge Newman
cited several nineteenth-century judicial statements that patents were
“property,” she nonetheless concluded that the justification for securing patents
as constitutional “private property” is based only on twentieth-century federal
legislation and case law.
33
Amazingly, even the jurists who advocate for
securing patents as constitutional private property are unaware of the
nineteenth-century jurisprudence directly addressing this vital constitutional
issue.
The limited scholarship on patent takings concludes that
Zoltek is on firmer
historical ground than either
Festo or the dissenting opinions by Judge Plager
and Judge Newman.
34
Some scholars have explored normative frameworks for
actual reasons for Congress adopting the predecessor statute to § 1498 indicate that this
would be an improper application of this canon.
See infra notes 124-35 and accompanying
text (discussing how 1910 predecessor statute to § 1498 was intended merely to ratify pre-
existing case law).
31
Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 464 F.3d 1335, 1336 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (Newman, J.,
dissenting);
Zoltek, 442 F.3d at 1374 (Plager, J., dissenting).
32
Zoltek, 442 F.3d at 1370-71 (Plager, J., dissenting) (footnote omitted).
33
Zoltek, 464 F.3d at 1336 (Newman, J., dissenting) (“Almost a century of precedent has
implemented the right of patentees to the remedies afforded to private property taken for
public use. There is no basis today to reject this principle.” (emphasis added)).
34
Most takings scholars neglect patents in favor of the land and chattels that dominate
modern takings jurisprudence.
See supra note 12 and accompanying text. Many intellectual
property scholars neglect the Takings Clause because they prefer to define patents as
something other than property.
See infra notes 47-51.
Surprisingly, many of the extant articles discussing patent takings (either directly or at
least in part) are recently published student comments addressing modern developments in
case law.
See, e.g., J. Nicholas Bunch, Note, Takings, Judicial Takings, and Patent Law, 83
T
EX. L. REV. 1747 (2005); Gordon Klancnik, Note, A Proposal To Resolve Infringement
Induced by Government Fiat
, 70 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 806 (2002); Daniel J. Melman,
Comment,
Patently Wrong: A Critical Analysis of Florida Prepaid Postsecondary Education
Expense Board v. College Savings Bank, 74 S
T. JOHNS L. REV. 875 (2000); Kurt E.
Springmann, Note,
The Impact of Seminole on Intellectual Property Infringement by State
Actors: The Interaction of Article I, Article III, the Eleventh Amendment, and the Fourteenth
Amendment
, 29 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 889 (1997); Robert C. Wilmoth, Note, Toward a Congruent
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 697
applying the Takings Clause to patents and other intellectual property rights.
35
Yet the conventional wisdom maintains that there are no instances of such
constitutional protection afforded to patents in the early historical record.
Recently, Thomas Cotter seemingly corrected the conventional wisdom by
highlighting a brief discussion of patent takings in 1881 in the Supreme
Court’s opinion in
James v. Campbell.
36
However, Cotter mistakenly claims
that this was the
first discussion of patent takings in the historical record, and
he further notes that it is difficult “to take at face value the Court’s
characterization . . . of unauthorized government uses of patents as takings”
because such statements were “only dicta.”
37
In fact, there is now some
confusion among scholars on whether the reference to patent takings in
James
was dicta or an essential part of its decision.
38
(Cotter is right that the
reference was dicta).
39
Despite this confusion, though, the few scholars who have written about the
James Court’s patent takings dicta agree with Cotter’s mistaken historical
claim that this was the first and only historical case to address this issue, and as
such they maintain that the patent takings issue remains “an unsettled
and Proportional Patent Law: Redressing State Patent Infringement After Florida Prepaid v.
College Savings Bank, 55 SMU L. R
EV. 519 (2002).
35
See Matthew S. Bethards, Condemning a Patent: Taking Intellectual Property by
Eminent Domain
, 32 AIPLA Q.J. 81 (2004); Daniel R. Cahoy, Patent Fences and
Constitutional Fence Posts: Property Barriers to Pharmaceutical Importation
, 15 FORDHAM
INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT. L.J. 623 (2005); Cotter, supra note 2, at 532-33; Shubha
Ghosh,
Patents and the Regulatory State: Rethinking the Patent Bargain Metaphor after
Eldred, 19 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 1315 (2004); Paul J. Heald & Michael L. Wells, Remedies
for the Misappropriation of Intellectual Property by State and Municipal Governments
Before and After Seminole Tribe: The Eleventh Amendment and Other Immunity Doctrines,
55 W
ASH. & LEE L. REV. 849 (1998); Roberta Rosenthal Kwall, Governmental Use of
Copyrighted Property: The Sovereign’s Prerogative
, 67 TEX. L. REV. 685 (1989).
36
104 U.S. 356, 358 (1881).
37
Cotter, supra note 2, at 541-43 (claiming that James is “the first of these decisions” in
which the Court considered patents takings). This same mistaken historical claim is
reiterated in Cotter’s follow-on scholarship on patent takings. See Christina Bohannan &
Thomas F. Cotter,
When the State Steals Ideas: Is the Abrogation of State Sovereign
Immunity from Federal Infringement Claims Constitutional in Light of
Seminole Tribe?, 67
F
ORDHAM L. REV. 1435, 1462 & n.177 (1999).
38
See Heald & Wells, supra note 35, at 857 (referring to the patent takings statements in
James as part of the Court’s holding). Other scholars have repeated Heald and Wells’s
mistaken claim that the patent takings discussion in
James was part of its decision. See,
e.g.
, Richard V. Adkisson, Intellectual Property & Eminent Domain: If Ever the Twain
Shall Meet
, 36 J. ECON. ISSUES 41, 46 (2002) (citing Heald and Wells for the claim that the
James Court “ruled for the inventor . . . that patents could not be appropriated without just
compensation”).
39
See infra note 105 and accompanying text (discussing why the patent takings
statements in
James were dicta).
698 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
question.”
40
For instance, takings scholars Thomas Merrill and David Dana
agree with Cotter and other intellectual property scholars that the “application
of the Takings Clause to intellectual property trademarks, copyrights and
patents has not yet been seriously tested in the courts.”
41
With respect to
patents, a recent article asks: “Does the Takings Clause apply to patents?
Unsurprisingly, there is no clear answer.”
42
Some scholars believe that the Takings Clause might be applicable to
patents, but that this can only be “derived through analogies to tangible
property as well as the implicit treatment by the courts.”
43
If the Takings
Clause is applicable to patents, the argument typically goes, then it is only by
virtue of extending the Supreme Court’s 1984 decision in
Ruckelshaus v.
Monsanto Co
.
44
that trade secrets are “private property” secured under the
Takings Clause.
45
The reasoning is relatively straightforward: if trade secrets
are constitutional private property, then, all things being equal, “the same goes
for patents” because both are forms of intellectual property.
46
Broader intellectual property scholarship critical of the expansive
protections afforded to patents, copyrights, and other intellectual property
rights today takes a similar tack in suggesting that the historical record is
inconclusive or contrary to the notion that patents are constitutional private
property. Relying on a historical claim that patents and copyrights were
40
Wilmoth, supra note 34, at 564; cf. Heald & Wells, supra note 35, at 857 (stating that
there is “scarce case law on the subject,” and asserting that
James is insufficient by itself to
establish a strong claim that intellectual property is constitutional private property).
41
DANA & MERRILL, supra note 2, at 233. Interestingly, they cite James in their
discussion of patent takings.
Id.
42
Bunch, supra note 34, at 1752.
43
Cahoy, supra note 35, at 678; see also Bethards, supra note 35, at 85-88 (describing
compensated takings of contracts, goodwill, and trade secrets as the bases for applying the
Takings Clause to patents); Ghosh, supra note 2, at 667 (claiming that applying the Takings
Clause to “intellectual property or intangible property would occur only through analogy”).
44
467 U.S. 986 (1984).
45
See, e.g., DANA & MERRILL, supra note 2, at 236 (stating that Ruckelshaus v.
Monsanto Co.
is the leading modern precedent”); Bunch, supra note 34, at 1752-53
(commenting that the characteristics of trade secrets identified by the
Monsanto Court as
justifying treating these entitlements as “property” under the Takings Clause are equally true
for patents); Cahoy, supra note 35, at 681 (stating that “[i]f there is any argument to be
made for the application of a regulatory takings scheme [to patents], it would likely be based
in the Supreme Court’s rather curious decision in
Ruckelshaus v. Monsanto”); Cotter, supra
note 2, at 537 (describing Monsanto as “the only recent United States Supreme Court case
dealing with an alleged taking of intellectual property”);
see also Zoltek Corp. v. United
States, 464 F.3d 1335, 1338 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (Newman, J., dissenting) (citing
Ruckelshaus
as supporting her belief that patents are secured under the Takings Clause).
46
Bunch, supra note 34, at 1753; cf. Heald & Wells, supra note 35, at 861 (“If trade
secrets are property for the purposes of Fifth Amendment Takings Clause analysis, then
copyrights and trademarks certainly are as well.”).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 699
special, limited monopoly grants in the early American Republic,
47
scholars
today condemn recent expansions in intellectual property rights,
48
which they
refer to as “propertizing” intellectual property.
49
They also criticize the use of
“property rhetoric” in intellectual property doctrines today, which they
consider both a novel practice and a contributing factor in the “propertization”
of intellectual property doctrines.
50
Thus, a traditional legal historian recently
noted the historical claim in intellectual property scholars’ lamenting “the
47
See, e.g., LAWRENCE LESSIG, THE FUTURE OF IDEAS 58-59, 94-96 (2001) (claiming that
early Americans viewed patents and copyrights as special, limited monopolies); S
IVA
VAIDHYANATHAN, COPYRIGHTS AND COPYWRONGS 23-24 (2001) (maintaining that early
Americans viewed patents and copyrights as “a necessary evil” in that these monopolies
provided limited incentives); Tyler T. Ochoa & Mark Rose,
The Anti-Monopoly Origins of
the Patent & Copyright Clause
, 84 J. PAT. & TRADEMARK OFF. SOCY 909, 919 (2002)
(arguing generally that patents and copyrights were viewed by early Americans as limited
monopolies);
see also Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 246 (2003) (Breyer, J., dissenting)
(castigating the
Eldred majority for ignoring the views of Madison, Jefferson “and others in
the founding generation, [who] warned against the dangers of monopolies” in granting
copyrights and patents).
48
See, e.g., Diamond v. Diehr, 450 U.S. 175 (1981) (holding that computer programs are
patentable subject matter); Diamond v. Chakrabarty, 447 U.S. 303 (1980) (holding that a
genetically engineered bacteria is patentable subject matter); State St. Bank & Trust Co. v.
Signature Fin. Group, Inc., 149 F.3d 1368 (Fed. Cir. 1998) (holding that business methods
are patentable subject matter).
49
See, e.g., Michael A. Carrier, Cabining Intellectual Property Through a Property
Paradigm
, 54 DUKE L.J. 1, 1 (2004) (declaring that “[o]ne of the most revolutionary legal
changes in the past generation has been the ‘propertization’ of intellectual property,” in
which such rights are viewed as “absolute property” and the “duration and scope of rights
expand without limit”); Mark A. Lemley,
Romantic Authorship and the Rhetoric of
Property
, 75 TEX. L. REV. 873, 902 (1997) (book review) (concluding after a survey of
increasing intellectual property protections that “the ‘propertization’ of intellectual property
is a very bad idea”); see also Pamela Samuelson, Information as Property: Do Ruckelshaus
and Carpenter Signal a Changing Direction in Intellectual Property Law?, 38 CATH. U. L.
R
EV. 365, 398 (1989) (describing and critiquing the “more proprietarian and anti-
dissemination attitude toward information than that which the law has previously
displayed”).
50
See, e.g., Anupam Chander & Madhavi Sunder, The Romance of the Public Domain,
92 C
AL. L. REV. 1331, 1343 (2004) (commenting on how it is “fashionable” today among
intellectual property scholars to believe that “the public domain stands in opposition to
intellectual property that the public domain is a bulwark against propertization and an
alternative to intellectual property”); Mark A. Lemley,
Property, Intellectual Property, and
Free Riding
, 83 TEX. L. REV. 1031, 1033 (2005) (stating that “[t]he idea of propertization
begins with a fundamental shift in the terminology of intellectual property law,” as “only
recently has the term ‘intellectual property’ come into vogue”); Lemley, supra note 49, at
895-904 (discussing the analytical and legal implications of using “property rhetoric” in
intellectual property policy debates).
700 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
‘propertization’ of the field,” in which the “expansive language of property
rights has displaced the traditional discourse of limited monopoly.”
51
This general historical claim in intellectual property scholarship supports the
more specific historical arguments at the patent-takings nexus. Simply put, if
patents were traditionally defined as limited monopoly privileges, then
nineteenth-century courts would not have extended constitutional protection to
them as property rights on par with common law rights in land or chattels.
Thus, the
Festo Court’s allusion that patents are constitutional private property,
or the similar arguments by Judge Plager and Judge Newman in their
Zoltek
dissents, is unprecedented, at least as a matter of constitutional doctrine and
historical practice. Although the
Festo Court, Judge Plager, and Judge
Newman may disagree with their critics as a matter of normative policy, they
would likely concur with their critics on this descriptive claim: patents have
never been secured under the Takings Clause.
It is unusual that a substantial historical development in constitutional law
involving two provisions of the Constitution the Takings Clause and the
Copyright and Patent Clause has been eclipsed so dramatically in modern
jurisprudence and scholarship. Adding to the mystery, there is nothing to
suggest that this is intentional. In fact, Judges Plager and Newman would have
benefited from invoking the long-standing nineteenth-century cases supporting
their arguments. This Article will conclude with some observations as to how
this situation arose, but first it will explicate the substantial nineteenth-century
jurisprudence addressing the issue of patent takings, reaching as far back as
antebellum Supreme Court decisions.
II. T
HE HISTORY OF PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY
Nineteenth-century courts concluded that patents were constitutional private
property based on a logical development in both patent and constitutional law.
As a doctrinal matter, courts need two constitutional predicates to secure rights
under the Takings Clause: first, courts must classify the legal entitlement as
“property,” because the Takings Clause secures only “private property;”
52
and
second, a property owner must have the ability to bring the government into
court as a defendant.
53
Perhaps unsurprisingly, the conclusion in the late
nineteenth century that the Takings Clause protected patents was based on a
jurisprudence that first focused on these two constitutional requirements.
51
Morton J. Horwitz, Conceptualizing the Right of Access to Technology, 79 WASH. L.
R
EV. 105, 114 (2004) (discussing the work of William Fisher).
52
U.S. CONST. amend. V.
53
This jurisdictional requirement is fundamental to the judicial enforcement of many
constitutional rights.
See, e.g., 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (2000) (providing a right to sue for “the
deprivation of any rights, privileges, or immunities secured by the Constitution and laws”).
However, the Supreme Court has since held that the Takings Clause is a self-executing
constitutional provision, and thus this second jurisdictional requirement has been mooted.
See Jacobs v. United States, 290 U.S. 13 (1933).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 701
Unfortunately, this jurisprudence has been lost to courts and scholars today.
Thus, it is necessary to recount this historical progression in long-forgotten
case law in order to understand the justification for this constitutional
proposition.
With respect to the first requirement the identification of patents as
property nineteenth-century case law dating back to the antebellum period
unequivocally classified patents as property rights. As I have explained
elsewhere, early Congresses and courts identified patents as
property, and
invoked natural-rights justifications for property in defining and adjudicating
patent rights.
54
Moreover, as a doctrinal matter, courts throughout the early to
mid-nineteenth century explicitly relied on
real property case law, and often
invoked property concepts, such as trespass and the inchoate-choate right
distinction, in adjudicating patent cases.
55
Substantively and rhetorically,
nineteenth-century courts believed that patents were a species of property.
56
Yet constitutional scholars know that merely classifying a legal entitlement
as
property is insufficient by itself to justify its constitutional protection. This
was as true in the nineteenth century as it is today. For instance, antebellum
courts defined the legal rights secured under monopoly franchises as
property,
but they nevertheless denied franchisees’ claims to constitutional protection
when the government interfered with their property rights.
57
They also limited
constitutional protections afforded to traditional, tangible private property
deemed to be “affected with the public interest.”
58
Identifying patents as
54
See generally Mossoff, Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege,” supra note 11.
55
Id. at 992-98.
56
Id.; see, e.g., Allen v. New York, 1 F. Cas. 506, 508 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1879) (No. 232)
(noting that “the [patent] right is a species of property”); Ball v. Withington, 2 F. Cas. 556,
557 (C.C.S.D. Ohio 1874) (No. 815) (noting that patents are a “species of property”); Jones
v. Sewall, 13 F. Cas. 1017, 1020 (C.C.D. Me. 1873) (No. 7,495),
rev’d on other grounds, 91
U.S. (1 Otto) 171 (1875) (explaining that “[i]nventions lawfully secured by letters patent are
the property of the inventors, and as such . . . are as much entitled to legal protection as any
other species of property”); Carew v. Boston Elastic Fabric Co., 5 F. Cas. 56, 57 (C.C.D.
Mass. 1871) (No. 2,398) (stating that “the rights conferred by the patent law, being property,
have the incidents of property”); Gay v. Cornell, 10 F. Cas. 110, 112 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1849)
(No. 5,280) (recognizing that “an invention is, within the contemplation of the patent laws, a
species of property”).
57
See, e.g., Proprietors of the Charles River Bridge v. Proprietors of the Warren Bridge,
36 U.S. (11 Pet.) 420 (1837) (rejecting a bridge franchisee’s argument that Massachusetts’
granting of another bridge franchise over the same river was a violation of its
constitutionally secured property and contract rights);
cf. Brown v. Barry, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.)
365, 367 (1797) (stating the canon applied in
Charles River Bridge that a monopoly grant
obtained by a legislative “act . . . being in derogation of the common law, is to be taken
strictly”).
58
Munn v. Illinois, 94 U.S. 113, 126 (1876) (quoting Matthew Hale, A Treatise in Three
Parts
, in 1 A COLLECTION OF TRACTS RELATIVE TO THE LAW OF ENGLAND 1, 78 (Francis
Hargrave ed., Dublin 1787). Although the plaintiff property owner relied on the Fourteenth
Amendment, and the Court’s decision was limited to this particular claim, Chief Justice
702 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
property was necessary in securing these legal entitlements under the Takings
Clause, but it was not sufficient.
In 1843 in
McClurg v. Kingsland,
59
the Supreme Court began laying the
groundwork for applying the Takings Clause to the property rights secured in
patents, as distinguished from monopoly franchises and other similarly limited
property rights. Although not a takings case, the
McClurg Court held that
Congress could not
retroactively limit property rights that had been secured in
now-repealed patent statutes. Justice Baldwin’s opinion for the unanimous
Court acknowledged that “the powers of Congress to legislate upon the subject
of patents is plenary by the terms of the Constitution.”
60
Nonetheless, he
concluded that a “repeal [of a patent statute] can have no effect to impair the
right of property then existing in a patentee, or his assignee, according to the
well-established principles of this court.”
61
In sum, a patent issued under now-
repealed statutes vested property rights in an inventor,
62
so that “the patent
must therefore stand as if the [now-repealed] acts . . . remained in force.”
63
In defending the vested property rights in patents, Justice Baldwin relied on
the “well-established principles of this court,”
64
citing only the Court’s earlier
decision in
Society for the Propagation of the Gospel in Foreign Parts v. Town
of New Haven
.
65
Significantly, Society addressed neither takings nor patents; it
adjudicated the status of property rights in land after the Revolutionary War.
In this case, the Court held that “the termination of a treaty cannot devest rights
of property already vested under it.”
66
A contrary rule, declared the unanimous
Society Court, “would overturn the best established doctrines of law, and sap
the very foundation on which property rests.”
67
In relying on such “well-
Waite referenced the Takings Clause in his decision. See id. at 125. Thus, Munn is an
example of the general proposition that legal property rights are neither universally nor
absolutely secured under the Constitution.
59
42 U.S. (1 How.) 202 (1843).
60
Id. at 206.
61
Id. (emphasis added); see also In re Fultz, 9 F. Cas. 998, 1001 (C.C.D.C. 1853) (No.
5,156) (discussing the repeal of provisions of the 1836 Patent Act by the 1839 Patent Act,
and explaining that there is “nothing in the repealing act of 1839 which takes away or
impairs [the patentee’s] right; on the contrary, [there is] every reason to infer that it was
intended to be saved and secured to the fullest extent”).
62
See, e.g., Gayler v. Wilder, 51 U.S. (10 How.) 477, 493 (1850) (recognizing that an
inventor is “vested by law with an inchoate right . . . which he may perfect and make
absolute” by obtaining a patent); Evans v. Jordan, 8 F. Cas. 872, 873-74 (C.C.D. Va. 1813)
(No. 4,564) (Marshall, Circuit Justice) (explaining that an inventor has an “inchoate
property which [is] vested by the discovery” and which is ultimately “perfected by the
patent”).
63
McClurg, 42 U.S. at 206.
64
Id.
65
21 U.S. (8 Wheat.) 464 (1823).
66
Id. at 493.
67
Id. at 494.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 703
established principles” set forth in
Society, the McClurg Court directly linked
patents with traditional property rights as a matter of legal and constitutional
doctrine.
Beginning in the early 1870s, the Court built on these antebellum decisions
and laid the groundwork for satisfying the second requirement for securing
patents as constitutional private property – establishing a patentee’s right to sue
the government for an unauthorized use of a patent as a taking of private
property. The process began with
United States v. Burns,
68
in which the Court
affirmed the Court of Claims’ decision to award damages to a patentee for an
unauthorized governmental use of his patented invention. Congress created the
Court of Claims in 1855, providing a venue for citizens to sue the government
for breach of their contract or property rights.
69
Accordingly, if patentees
could sue for violations of their property rights by the federal government, then
they could bring suit only in the Court of Claims.
70
In representing the United
States, the Solicitor General argued that the “government may have acted
tortiously in making [the invention] under the patent when it had no right by
contract to do so. But for relief against such action, Congress is the body to
68
79 U.S. (12 Wall.) 246 (1870). This is an interesting case that arose, in part, from
circumstances surrounding the Civil War. Burns brought suit in the Court of Claims after
the federal government refused to pay royalties to him, as an assignee under a contract for
the manufacture and use of a patented tent. The contract was executed in 1858 between the
original patentee, H.H. Sibley, and the U.S. government. Shortly thereafter, Sibley assigned
one-half interest to Burns. At that time, Sibley and Burns were both Majors in the U.S.
Army. When the Civil War commenced two years later, Major Sibley resigned his
commission and joined the Confederacy, and thus the
Burns Court concluded that he lost his
right to claim his one-half royalties under his patent “by reason of his disloyalty.”
Id. at
254. Major Burns, however, was permitted to prosecute his claim for his one-half royalties,
because he “remained true to his allegiance and served in the army of the Union.” Id. at
248. The Civil War not only pitted brother against brother, as the old saying goes, but also
patentee against assignee.
69
See Act of Feb. 24, 1855, ch. 122, 10 Stat. 612 (1855).
70
According to its enabling statute, the Court of Claims could hear “all claims founded
upon any law of Congress, or upon any regulation of an executive department, or upon any
contract, express or implied, with the government of the United States.” Id. § 1, 10 Stat. at
612. This provision ultimately forced courts to exploit “implied contract” as a legal fiction
by which a patentee could sue the government for unauthorized uses, because courts
construed “law of Congress” as referring to a specific statutory authorization for payment of
damages by the government. See Great Falls Mfg. Co. v. Garland, 124 U.S. 581, 598-99
(1888); Pitcher v. United States, 1 Ct. Cl. 7, 10-11 (1863). Moreover, this jurisdictional
statute did not provide for recovery for a tort, such as patent infringement.
See James v.
Campbell, 104 U.S. 356, 358-59 (1881);
see also Cotter, supra note 2, at 543-44 (discussing
this aspect of the Court of Claims’ jurisdiction over patents). Notably, this procedural
fiction was not only applied to patentees, as the Supreme Court also invoked the fiction of
an “implied contract” in establishing the Court of Claims’ jurisdiction over takings claims
concerning real property.
See United States v. Great Falls Mfg. Co., 112 U.S. 645, 656-57
(1884).
704 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
address.”
71
The Supreme Court summarily rejected this argument. Consistent
with
McClurg, the Burns Court concluded that “the government cannot, after
the patent is issued, make use of the improvement any more than a private
individual, without license of the inventor
or making compensation to him.”
72
Six years later in Cammeyer v. Newton,
73
the Supreme Court considered the
question of whether federal officials were immunized from a claim for
infringement under the patent statutes when they used patented inventions
without the patentee’s permission.
74
The Cammeyer defendants were federal
officials who defended their actions, in part, by claiming sovereign immunity
from infringement claims because they acted within the scope of their official
authority. The
Cammeyer Court thus recognized that it had to address the
defendants’ immunity claim as a “[p]reliminary” procedural matter “[b]efore
comparing the patented machine with the apparatus used bythe defendants in
the substantive infringement analysis.
75
In so doing, the Court soundly
rejected the defendants’ immunity argument, stating pointedly that “[a]gents of
the public have no more right to take such private property than other
individuals.”
76
Citing Burns, the Cammeyer Court declared that “[p]rivate
property, the Constitution provides, shall not be taken for public use without
just compensation,”
77
which it held applicable to patentees suffering an
“invasion of the private rights of individuals.”
78
The nascent takings principles expressed in Burns, Cammeyer, and McClurg
came to fruition in the famous and oft-cited takings decision in McKeever’s
Case
,
79
which squarely addressed the question of whether the Takings Clause
secured patents as private property, requiring just compensation upon an
unauthorized use by the government. Similar to
Cammeyer, the plaintiff-
patentee, Samuel McKeever, sued the U.S. government in the Court of Claims,
71
Burns, 79 U.S. at 251.
72
Id. at 252 (emphasis added).
73
94 U.S. 225 (1876).
74
Id. at 226-27. In this case, Cammeyer was an assignee of a patented device for
dredging waterways, which federal agents used with neither his permission nor a license.
Id. at 226-30.
75
Id. at 234.
76
Id. at 234-35.
77
Id. at 234.
78
Id. at 235. Justice Clifford signaled in the first paragraph of his opinion that this
would be his conclusion on this issue when he wrote that “an invention so secured [under
the patent statutes] is property in the holder of the patent, and that as such the right of the
holder is as much entitled to protection as any other property.”
Id. at 226.
79
McKeever v. United States (McKeever’s Case), 14 Ct. Cl. 396 (1878). There appears
to be no formal record of an appeal to the Supreme Court, but twenty-three years later,
Justice McKenna would cite McKeever with the remark, “affirmed on appeal by this court.”
Russell v. United States, 182 U.S. 516, 531 (1901);
see also United States v. Buffalo Pitts
Co., 234 U.S. 228, 233 (1914) (citing
McKeever with a similar remark that it was “affirmed
by this court”).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 705
alleging an unconstitutional taking of his property without compensation.
80
McKeever claimed that the U.S. War Department manufactured and used two
of his patented inventions without his authorization.
81
The government
repeated its defense from
Cammeyer, claiming sovereign immunity and
arguing that patents, as special grants of legal privileges
from the government,
did not apply
against the government.
82
Relying explicitly on Cammeyer,
Burns, and McClurg, the McKeever court rejected this argument and firmly
placed patents within the scope of private property rights secured under the
Takings Clause.
83
The McKeever court agreed with the government that patents representing
the “property in the mind-work of the inventor” – were not protected at
common law, and that their origin was found in the English Crown’s royal
prerogative to grant manufacturing monopolies.
84
The court noted that
England remained wedded to the view of a patent as “a grant” issuing solely
from “royal favor,” and therefore it “shall not exclude a use[] by the Crown.”
85
But this was not the law in the now-independent United States of America.
Contrary to the English patent practice, the
McKeever court pointed out,
American patents secured the “mind-work which we term inventions,” as
specifically authorized under the Copyright and Patent Clause in the
Constitution (what the court referred to as “our organic law”).
86
80
See McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 416-17. Given the formal pleading requirements for
plaintiff property owners filing takings claims in the Court of Claims, McKeever was forced
to argue the legal fiction of an “implied contract” in his complaint. Id.; see also supra note
70 (explaining how landowners and patentees suing the government for a taking in the Court
of Claims had to claim an “implied contract” due to Congress’s use of imprecise language in
the Court of Claims’ 1855 enabling legislation).
81
McKeever was a Lieutenant in the U.S. Army, and he had invented a new cartridge
box that aided soldiers in carrying more ammunition and in retrieving this ammunition in
the field. He obtained two patents in 1873 for this invention. McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 397.
82
See id. at 417-20 (discussing English political history and case law establishing that
the Crown was privileged in using patented inventions without authorization).
83
See id. at 422 (citing McClurg, Burns, and Cammeyer).
84
Id. at 417-18. This was an uncontroversial historical observation. See, e.g., Morton v.
N.Y. Eye Infirmary, 17 F. Cas. 879, 881 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1862) (No. 9,865) (noting that “[a]t
common law an inventor has no exclusive right to his invention or discovery”); Motte v.
Bennett, 17 F. Cas. 909, 913-14 (C.C.D.S.C. 1849) (No. 9,884) (Wayne, Circuit Justice)
(discussing history of patents as “privileges and monopolies” granted by “the kings of
England”);
see also Mossoff, Rethinking the Development of Patents, supra note 11, at
1259-76 (describing progenitor of modern patent system in English Crown’s practice of
granting manufacturing monopolies).
85
McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 420.
86
Id.; see U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8 (“The Congress shall have Power . . . . [t]o promote the
Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.”).
706 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
The
McKeever court first analyzed the text of the Copyright and Patent
Clause as evidence of this fundamental distinction in patent law between the
English Crown’s
personal privilege and the American property right.
87
The
court explained that the language in this constitutional provision the use of
the terms “right” and “exclusive,” the absence of the term “patent,” and the
absence of any express reservation in favor of the government established
that the property rights secured in an American patent were not on the same
legal footing as the personal privileges secured by the English Crown.
88
This
conclusion was further buttressed by the fact that the Framers empowered
Congress, not the Executive, to secure an inventor’s rights – placing this
constitutional provision in Article I, not in Article II which suggested they
viewed patents as important property rights secured by the people’s
representatives, not as a special grant issued by the prerogative of the
Executive.
89
Although the Framers did not state their reasons for securing
patents in the Constitution, the
McKeever court concluded that “they had a
clear apprehension of the English law, on the one hand, and a just conception,
on the other, of what one of the commentators on the Constitution has termed
‘a natural right to the fruits of mental labor.’”
90
Invoking this classic formulation of the natural right to property,
91
the
McKeever court then canvassed the federal government’s interpretation of the
Copyright and Patent Clause in the century since the Founding Era, finding
again that patents protected important property rights, not special grants of
personal privilege. Accordingly, Congress’s enactment of the patent statutes,
the Executive’s use of patented articles via “express contracts,” and the
Judiciary’s interpretation of these statutes and contracts all “forbid the
assumption that this government has ever sought to appropriate the property of
87
See McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 420-21; see also Belding v. Turner, 3 F. Cas. 84, 85
(C.C.D. Conn. 1871) (No. 1,243) (distinguishing the “personal privilege” granted in an
English patent from the “incorporeal chattel” or “personal estate” secured under the U.S.
patent laws).
88
McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 421.
89
Id. at 420.
90
Id. Judge Nott did not provide a citation for this quote, but he was likely paraphrasing
from a recently published treatise.
See THEODORE D. WOOLSEY ET AL., THE FIRST CENTURY
OF THE
REPUBLIC: AREVIEW OF AMERICAN PROGRESS 443 (New York, Harper & Bros. 1876)
(discussing how inventors are given “some control over the reproduction of the fruits of
mental labor” on the basis of “public policy” and “the natural right of property, by authority
of which they might, if they chose, keep what they produce themselves instead of
disseminating it”).
91
See, e.g., Vanhorne’s Lessee v. Dorrance, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 304, 310 (1795) (Patterson,
J.) (“[T]he right of acquiring and possessing property, and having it protected, is one of the
natural, inherent, and unalienable rights of man. . . . No man would become a member of a
community, in which he could not enjoy the fruits of his honest labour and industry.”).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 707
the inventor.”
92
The McKeever court expressly cited Cammeyer, Burns, and
McClurg Supreme Court authority establishing the necessary predicates for
the
McKeever court to conclude that the Takings Clause secured patents as
constitutional private property.
93
But McKeever seemed to blithely sweep under the rug a fundamental
difference between patents secured under federal statute and traditional,
tangible property rights secured at common law. This difference in doctrinal
provenance – statute versus common law would seem to suggest that patents
were insufficiently similar to traditional property rights to justify their
protection under the Takings Clause.
McKeever’s failure to acknowledge this
point, let alone address it, raises the specter that its reasoning was more the
result of hyperbolic rhetoric and late-nineteenth-century judicial formalism
than of substantive patent and constitutional doctrine.
In fact, this distinction between statutory and common law property was
well known in the nineteenth century, and the Supreme Court placed its
imprimatur on it in an 1834 copyright case.
94
Federal officials also invoked
this distinction in the patent context. At a minimum, it was implicit in both
Cammeyer and McKeever, in which the government defended its actions by
equating patent rights created under federal statute with patent privileges
granted by the English Crown.
95
Other federal officials defended themselves
against takings claims by invoking this distinction explicitly, such as in
Campbell v. James,
96
decided soon after McKeever. In Campbell, U.S. postal
officials defended their unauthorized use of a patented device for postmarking
and canceling hand-stamps by asserting several claims, including a challenge
to the patent’s validity that the Supreme Court ultimately found compelling.
97
Significantly for our purposes, the defendants also claimed that they were
immune from suit because patent rights were created by federal statutes
adopted and enforced by the federal government, and thus such legal rights
92
McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 421; see also Mossoff, Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege,
supra
note 11, at 992-98 (discussing how antebellum and mid-nineteenth-century courts
treated patents as property rights both procedurally and substantively).
93
McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 422. Notably, a concurrence by Judge Hunt and a dissent by
Judge Davis, joined by Chief Judge Drake, all left untouched Judge Nott’s disquisition on
the nature of American patents as constitutional private property. Instead, judges Hunt,
Davis, and Drake contested only the damages set by Judge Nott for the government’s
unauthorized use of McKeever’s patented cartridge box. See id. at 431 (Hunt, J.,
concurring);
id. at 431-34 (Davis, J., dissenting).
94
Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. (8 Pet.) 591, 660-61 (1834) (holding that patents are not
secured as common law rights and are merely statutory rights created by Congress under the
authority granted to it under the Constitution).
95
See Cammeyer v. Newton, 94 U.S. 225, 234-35 (1876); McKeever, 14 Ct. Cl. at 420.
96
4 F. Cas. 1168 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1879) (No. 2,361), rev’d on other grounds, James v.
Campbell, 104 U.S. 356 (1881).
97
James, 104 U.S. at 382-83 (holding that the reissued patent was “inoperative and
void”).
708 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
were not enforceable against agents of the federal government in a federal
court.
98
The Campbell court found the defendants’ sovereign immunity argument
wanting in much the same manner as the
McKeever court did. Although there
is no evidence that the
Campbell court was aware of the McKeever decision,
Campbell relied on the same case law in summarizing the legal status of
patents: “The property in a patented invention stands the same as other
property, in this respect.”
99
By itself, of course, this proposition does not
refute defendants’ claim to sovereign immunity, but the
Campbell court
quickly drew the logical implication of this observation:
[The patent] was granted by express law of congress, pursuant to the
constitution, without which it could not exist. But, all property is upheld
by law, either expressly or impliedly enacted or adopted, all of which is
the law of the land, the same as the statutes upholding patents are. This
property, like all other private property recognized by law, is exempt
from being taken for public use without just compensation, by the
supreme law of the land.
100
The ease with which Cammeyer, Campbell, and McKeever consistently and
unequivocally held that patents were constitutional private property reveals the
extent to which this proposition was well grounded in the constitutional and
patent jurisprudence at that time.
But this is not the end of the story. The defendants appealed the
Campbell
court’s decision in favor of the patentee, and they ultimately succeeded in
convincing the Supreme Court that the patent at issue in the lawsuit was
invalid.
101
Since the Supreme Court resolved James v. Campbell on the issue
of the patent’s validity, it addressed only as dicta whether patents were secured
under the Takings Clause. Here, the
James Court agreed with the lower court,
stating “we have no doubt” that the “exclusive property in the patented
invention . . . cannot be appropriated or used by the government itself, without
just compensation, any more than it can appropriate or use without
compensation land.”
102
The evolution from Society and McClurg, through
Burns, Cammeyer, McKeever, and Campbell, appears to reach its apogee in
James. With the Supreme Court’s imprimatur, the conclusion seemed clear
that patents were secured as constitutional private property under the Takings
Clause.
98
See Campbell, 4 F. Cas. at 1172.
99
Id. (citing Burns and Cammeyer); cf. Carr v. Rice, 5 F. Cas. 140, 146 (C.C.S.D.N.Y.
1856) (No. 2,440) (charging a jury that the first inventor has prior title to any subsequent
inventors and that “[p]atent interests are not distinguishable, in this respect, from other kinds
of property”).
100
Campbell, 4 F. Cas. at 1172.
101
See James, 104 U.S. at 382-83.
102
Id. at 358.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 709
Yet
James ultimately sowed doubt where McKeever and Campbell had
found clarity. Although
James acknowledged that patents are property within
the ambit of the Takings Clause, it proceeded to undermine the second
requirement for securing patents under the Constitution questioning whether
there was a federal court authorized to rule on this constitutional claim by a
patentee. Apparently forgetting the Court’s own prior decisions on this issue,
Justice Bradley mused in his
James opinion “whether such an action can be
sustained” given the absence of a statute granting jurisdiction to a federal court
to hear a takings claim by a patentee.
103
Admittedly, it is possible that James implicitly reversed the earlier cases, but
the full context of Justice Bradley’s remarks belies this suggestion. First, it is
revealing that Justice Bradley cited only a single case in support of this
observation; it was not even a patent case, but rather one involving an estoppel
defense in a land dispute.
104
It is unlikely that the James Court intended to
overrule
McKeever, Cammeyer, Burns, or McClurg when it acted as if this
jurisprudence, reaching back to the antebellum era, did not even exist. In fact,
the absence of any references to
McKeever, Cammeyer, Burns, or McClurg is
striking, particularly given that the circuit court cited
Burns and Cammeyer in
the decision on appeal.
Second, and more significant, Justice Bradley’s musings were only dicta, as
the Court ended its brief discussion of the takings issue by noting that “the
conclusion which we have reached in this case does not render it necessary to
decide this question.”
105
Perhaps the Justices did not feel compelled to review
the Court’s own precedents on this constitutional issue given that it was
unnecessary to decide the case before them. In any event, it is difficult to
argue that these remarks were intended to overrule the prior patent takings
jurisprudence when they were made in dicta and without any consideration of
the substantial precedent directly on point.
106
In the end, though, Justice
Bradley’s unprecedented musings succeeded in muddying the waters, and
subsequent cases surprisingly relied on his dicta, treating it as part of the
holding of
James. The result was a spat of Supreme Court cases that called
into question the right of patentees to sue under the Takings Clause,
disregarding or simply missing the substantial pre-
James precedent directly
addressing this important constitutional issue.
107
103
Id. at 359.
104
Id. (citing Carr v. United States, 98 U.S. 433 (1878)).
105
Id.
106
Professor Cotter makes this same point, but for different effect. He accepts Justice
Bradley’s musings about patents and the Takings Clause at face value, and thus he too
misses all of the pre-James jurisprudence. Consequently, he mistakenly questions the
doctrinal significance of
James as setting forth any basis for patentees to claim a taking
upon an unauthorized use by the government.
See Cotter, supra note 2, at 543.
107
See, e.g., Palmer v. United States, 128 U.S. 262 (1888) (holding that patentees could
not sue except on the basis of a contract with the government, citing only
Burns);
710 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
Of course, it is important to recognize that nineteenth-century jurisprudence
was not monolithic in favor of securing patents under the Takings Clause.
There are some decisions that suggested otherwise, such as Judge Blatchford’s
allusion in 1869 that the U.S. government retained an implied reservation to
use a patent.
108
As in James, these remarks were not necessary to resolve the
case, as Judge Blatchford recognized that he did “not intend . . . to intimate an
opinion as to whether the government is or is not excluded from the right to
make for itself and use the patented invention without the consent of the
patentee.”
109
He did, however, reveal his personal view on the matter by
referencing a recently decided English case holding that British patents were a
“sole privilege” granted by “the crown,”
110
suggesting that American patentees
stood on equal legal footing as English patentees when faced with
unauthorized governmental uses of their inventions. Notably,
McKeever
recognized this distinction between English royal privileges and American
property rights as one of the principal differences between U.S. and British
patent law, concluding that American patents were secured under the Takings
Clause.
111
Notwithstanding Judge Blatchford’s minority view that patents were special
grants of privilege, the substance of nineteenth-century patent law followed the
logical progression necessary to secure patents under the Takings Clause. In
antebellum cases, such as
McClurg, the Supreme Court established that patents
were property rights on par with tangible property rights.
112
On the basis of
this doctrinal classification, the Court recognized in
Burns and Cammeyer that
the Court of Claims had jurisdiction to hear a patentee’s claim for unauthorized
uses by the government.
113
This evolution reached its climax in McKeever and
Campbell, in which both courts held that patents were constitutional private
property secured under the Takings Clause.
114
Although the James Court
muddied these clear waters when it forgot its own case law on the
jurisdictional issue, it still recognized that patents were property rights within
the scope of the Takings Clause.
115
Aside from Campbell’s reversal on patent
validity grounds, none of these nineteenth-century decisions have been
Schillinger v. United States, 155 U.S. 163 (1894) (holding, without any acknowledgement
of
Burns, Cammeyer, or McKeever, that patentees were precluded from suing under the
Takings Clause); Crozier v. Fried. Krupp Aktiengesellschaft, 224 U.S. 290 (1912)
(following the
Schillinger holding and citing only cases decided after James).
108
Heaton v. Quintard, 11 F. Cas. 1008, 1009 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1869) (No. 6,311).
109
Id.
110
Id. (citing Feathers v. The Queen, 12 Law T., N.S. 114 (1865)).
111
See supra notes 84-93 and accompanying text.
112
See supra notes 59-67 and accompanying text.
113
See supra notes 68-78 and accompanying text.
114
See supra notes 79-93, 96-100 and accompanying text.
115
See supra notes 102-07 and accompanying text.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 711
reversed or limited in subsequent years.
116
The nineteenth-century
jurisprudence was quite clear: patents were private property rights secured
under the Constitution.
Somehow this constitutional proposition is now long forgotten, resulting in
courts and scholars today treating the issue as one that is relatively novel and
vague. This raises an interesting question: why has the historical protection of
patents as constitutional private property become a forgotten legal artifact?
Although answering this question in its entirety would require an article in its
own right, this Article will conclude with some observations as to how this
situation might have come to pass as a matter of intellectual history.
III. P
ATENTS, PROPERTY AND CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY
P
AST AND PRESENT
The nineteenth-century jurisprudence discussed in this Article has not been
purposefully buried or neglected due to a nefarious conspiracy by modern anti-
property scholars and jurists. The cases are easily found through standard legal
research; in fact, twentieth-century courts and scholars have repeatedly cited to
McKeever, McClurg, and the other nineteenth-century decisions. McKeever, in
particular, is often cited for procedural issues or for the portion of its decision
addressing how courts should compute damages for patent infringement.
117
Yet, despite this obvious awareness of the
McKeever opinion, its substantial
discussion applying the Takings Clause to patents has gone completely
unnoticed in all modern judicial decisions, as well as in modern takings and
patent scholarship. What explains how this nineteenth-century jurisprudence
applying the Takings Clause to patents has fallen into such disrepute in the
modern era?
An easy doctrinal answer is that Congress mooted this jurisprudence with
the Tucker Act.
118
Enacted in 1887, the Tucker Act did not address patents
116
In fact, some of these cases are very much alive and in play in contemporary
intellectual property disputes. As recently as 2003, Supreme Court Justices argued
extensively over the scope of the McClurg holding in adjudicating a challenge to the 1998
Copyright Term Extension Act.
See Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003).
117
See, e.g., United States v. Buffalo Pitts Co., 234 U.S. 228, 233 (1914) (citing
McKeever for proposition that patentees may sue the government for unauthorized uses);
Bethlehem Steel Co. v. United States, 42 Ct. Cl. 365, 376 (1907) (same). Courts and
scholars, however, mostly rely on McKeever for its decision concerning how patent-
infringement damages should be assessed by courts on an implied-in-fact contract theory.
See, e.g., International Harvester Co. of America v. United States, 72 Ct. Cl. 707, 714
(1931); Lionel Marks Lavenue,
Patent Infringement Against the United States and
Government Contractors Under 28 U.S.C. § 1498 in the United States Court of Federal
Claims
, 2 J. INTELL. PROP. L. 389, 409-10 (1995); see also Amy L. Landers, Let the Games
Begin: Incentives to Innovation in the New Economy of Intellectual Property Law
, 46 SANTA
CLARA L. REV. 307, 317 (2006).
118
Act of Mar. 3, 1887, ch. 359, 24 Stat. 505 (codified as amended in 28 U.S.C. §§ 1491-
1509 (2000 & Supp. IV 2004)).
712 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
specifically; it granted general jurisdiction to the Court of Claims to hear “[a]ll
claims founded upon the Constitution of the United States or any law of
Congress” (with a few listed exceptions).
119
This confirms that there was
widespread concern in the late nineteenth century that the Court of Claims’
1855 enabling legislation fell short of establishing jurisdiction over cases
concerning constitutional violations of property and contract rights.
120
In the
early twentieth century, Congress twice amended the Tucker Act to provide
specifically for the right of patentees to sue the government in the Court of
Claims for unauthorized uses of their property.
121
This suggests that patentees
lacked constitutional security for their property until Congress enacted these
patent-specific provisions. The Federal Circuit ran with this doctrinal
explanation in its recent decision in
Zoltek, relying on the Tucker Act to deny
securing patents under the Takings Clause.
122
The Tucker Act holds sway over
modern courts and scholars, leading them away from rediscovering the
relevant historical jurisprudence on patents as constitutional private
property.
123
Yet once this nineteenth-century jurisprudence has been rediscovered, the
Tucker Act loses its explanatory power. In fact, this legislation raises more
questions than it answers, because the committee report for the 1910 patent-
related amendment to the Tucker Act expressly states that the federal
government was using patents without authorization “in flat violation of [the
Takings Clause] and the decisions of the Supreme Court.”
124
In support of this
claim, the committee repeatedly cited and quoted from these nineteenth-
century decisions, such as
Cammeyer and Burns, as well as McKeever and
others.
125
In the extensive and far-ranging congressional debates, the
amendment’s sponsor, Representative Currier, emphasized that the legislation
“does not create any liability; it simply gives a remedy upon an existing
119
Id.
120
See supra note 70 and accompanying text.
121
Act of July 1, 1918, ch. 114, 40 Stat. 704, 705 (1918) (codified as amended in 28
U.S.C. § 1498 (2000)); Act of June 26, 1910, ch. 423, 36 Stat. 851, 851-52 (1910) (codified
as amended in 28 U.S.C. § 1498 (2000)); see also supra notes 20-21 and accompanying text
(discussing 28 U.S.C. § 1498 and its application by the courts).
122
See supra notes 27-30 and accompanying text.
123
See, e.g., Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 464 F.3d 1335, 1337 (Fed. Cir. 2006)
(Newman, J., dissenting) (stating that, prior to the 1910 patent-related amendments to the
Tucker Act, “although patents were property, the only remedy for governmental
infringement was by appeal to Congress”); Lavenue,
supra note 117, at 395-96 (stating that
before the Tucker Act, there was little patentees could do “when the government converted
[their] intellectual property”).
124
H.R. REP. NO. 61-1288, at 3 (1910).
125
See id. at 1-4.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 713
liability.”
126
Ultimately, Congress intended the patent-related amendments to
the Tucker Act to
ratify the nineteenth-century jurisprudence establishing that
patents were constitutional private property.
Why then enact a patent-related amendment to the Tucker Act in 1910? It
appears that this legislation was based in some procedural questions
concerning how patentees could sue the government for unauthorized uses of
their property, revealing the extent to which Justice Baldwin’s musings in
James
127
and in its progeny, such as Schillinger, Crozier, and others
128
caused chaos in patent takings doctrine. Under the 1855 enabling legislation
creating the Court of Claims, patentees had recourse to this court for a takings
claim only by asserting an “implied contract” with the government,
129
and the
1910 congressional debates reveal that such legal fictions were losing their
appeal by the turn of the twentieth century.
130
(Interestingly, patentees were
not the only property owners required to employ such legal fictions under the
1855 enabling legislation. Landowners also had to assert the legal fiction of an
“implied contract” to sue the government in the Court of Claims for a taking of
their property.
131
) The only other means of remuneration for unauthorized
governmental uses of patented inventions was through private acts of
legislation, a device, the congressmen noted, proving less and less certain in
the modern age.
132
126
45 CONG. REC. 8755, 8756 (1910). Later in the debate, Representative Lenroot
responded to a criticism of the amendment that it “creates a favored class” by stating that
“this bill, giv[es] a remedy for a right that does exist.” Id. at 8770.
127
See supra notes 103-06 and accompanying text.
128
See supra note 107 and accompanying text.
129
See supra note 70 and accompanying text.
130
See 45 CONG. REC. 8780 (reporting a colloquy between Representatives Dalzell and
Mann on the difficulties in defining an “implied contract,” as distinguished from an express
contract or a straightforward violation of a property right); H.R. REP. NO. 61-1288, at 3
(describing past reliance by patentees on express or implied contract claims in suing the
government in the Court of Claims).
In
Schillinger v. United States, the majority and dissenting Justices specifically clashed
over the nature of the “implied contract” claim, as used by patentees.
See 155 U.S. 163, 172
(1894);
id. at 175-76 (Harlan, J., dissenting). After surveying some of the relevant case law,
the dissent accused the majority of failing to recognize that an implied contract claim
permitted a patentee to sue “for the value of specific property taken for public use by [a
government] officer . . . even if the taking was originally without the consent of the owner.”
Id. at 175-76 (Harlan, J., dissenting). In other words, an implied contract claim was a legal
fiction used by the courts to overcome the jurisdictional limitations created by the 1855
enabling legislation.
See supra note 70. This was a point lost on courts in the post-James
era.
131
See, e.g., United States v. Great Falls Mfg. Co., 112 U.S. 645, 656-57 (1884).
132
See 45 CONG. REC. 8758 (statement of Rep. Graham) (noting that patentees “stand
knocking at the doors of Congress vainly seeking justice for twenty, thirty, or fifty years”);
id. at 8767 (statement of Rep. Goldfogle) (opposing the bill, but agreeing with its
714 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
There was little doubt, though, among the congressmen supporting the 1910
patent bill that the Court of Claims was supposed to have been the venue in
which patentees could seek redress for “piracy” by the state.
133
Throughout the
congressional debates, congressmen repeatedly referenced the nineteenth-
century jurisprudence applying the Takings Clause to patents as evidence that
the Court of Claims was supposed to secure this vital property right under the
Constitution.
134
Thus, it is somewhat startling that modern courts and patent
scholars, who regularly cite to these congressional records, seem to miss these
omnipresent references to the nineteenth-century jurisprudence on patent
takings.
135
Although initially appealing as an answer to our conundrum, the Tucker Act
ultimately leaves us with even more questions. When the
Zoltek court cited to
the Tucker Act and its legislative history, as well as when patent and takings
scholars have similarly cited to this legislation, they should have discovered
the substantial references to the pre-
James jurisprudence applying the Takings
Clause to patents. How is it possible that they have missed this jurisprudence
both in the case reporters, and in the numerous quotes and cites in the
legislative history to the Tucker Act?
One possible answer is that the issue is not doctrinal, but rather conceptual.
In other words, courts and scholars have interpreted the Tucker Act in a
particular way because it fits better with their modern conception of property,
which is quite distinct from the conception of property in the nineteenth
century. Although this is certainly not the only reason, one explanation for the
proponents that the “work is too great in this House, and you do not get the time within the
brief period that Congress meets to consider each and every claim” by patentees).
133
Id. at 8783 (statement of Rep. Burke) (claiming that nothing could “justify this great
Government in leading in a practice of piracy in patents, in invading the rights and
despoiling the property of the genius”); id. at 8758 (statement of Rep. Graham) (“It is a bill
to require the United States Government to live up to the eighth commandment, ‘Thou shalt
not steal.’ What right have they to steal a man’s patent?”); see also infra note 162 (citing
nineteenth-century cases in which infringers were called “pirates”).
134
Representative Dalzell, for instance, declared at one point that “we all know, that in
the framing of the law which gives jurisdiction to the Court of Claims there was no intent to
preserve to the United States a right to infringe a patent by failing to provide in the law for a
remedy for the infringement of that patent.” 45 C
ONG. REC. 8780. Representative Dalzell
went on to quote at length from
Cammeyer, James, and Palmer. Id.
Later in the debate, Representative Olmsted would repeat the same point: “Other
individuals have been awarded the right to go into the Court of Claims and recover their
indebtedness from the Government, and I see no reason why the owner of the patent should
not have the same privilege, where his patent is taken without his consent.”
Id. at 8781-82.
135
See, e.g., Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 442 F.3d 1345, 1351 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (citing
the committee report for the 1910 amendment); Daniel R. Cahoy,
Treating the Legal Side
Effects of Cipro®: A Reevaluation of Compensation Rules for Government Takings of
Patent Rights, 40 AM. BUS. L.J. 125, 144-45 (2002) (discussing 1910 and 1918 amendments
and citing their legislative history); Lavenue,
supra note 117, at 411 (discussing 1910
amendment and citing its legislative history).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 715
eclipse of the nineteenth-century jurisprudence on patents as constitutional
private property is that it resulted from the intellectual history on property that
divides the nineteenth from the twentieth century.
136
As scholars have recognized, the turn of the twentieth century brought with
it a revolution in both political and legal theory. In politics, Progressivism
came into vogue,
137
and in law, Legal Realism soon reigned supreme.
138
This
political and legal sea change affected many legal doctrines, especially
property.
139
Following Wesley Hohfeld’s re-conceptualization of legal rights
as comprising analytically distinct, social relationships,
140
legal realists
redefined property as a set of “social relations,”
141
which later courts and
136
See Mossoff, Rethinking the Development of Patents, supra note 11, at 1257 (“The
validity or significance of constitutional, social, economic or institutional analyses of legal
history is not in doubt; intellectual history is not exclusive of these other approaches to
historical analysis.”).
137
See, e.g., HERBERT CROLY, THE PROMISE OF AMERICAN LIFE (1909); FRANK J.
G
OODNOW, POLITICS AND ADMINISTRATION (1900); WOODROW WILSON, THE NEW FREEDOM
(1913).
138
See, e.g., AMERICAN LEGAL REALISM (William W. Fisher III et al. eds., 1993); NEIL
DUXBURY, PATTERNS OF AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE 65-159 (1995); LAWRENCE M.
F
RIEDMAN, A HISTORY OF AMERICAN LAW 688-89 (2d ed. 1985); Brian Leiter, American
Legal Realism
, in THE BLACKWELL GUIDE TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW AND LEGAL THEORY
50 (Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson eds., 2005); Joseph William Singer, Legal
Realism Now
, 76 CAL. L. REV. 465 (1988) (reviewing LAURA KALMAN, LEGAL REALISM AT
YALE, 1927-1960 (1986)).
139
See GREGORY S. ALEXANDER, COMMODITY & PROPRIETY: COMPETING VISIONS OF
PROPERTY IN AMERICAN LEGAL THOUGHT, 1776-1970, at 311-51 (1997); Claeys, supra note
13, at 1604-44; Thomas W. Merrill,
Property and the Right to Exclude, 77 NEB. L. REV.
730, 737-39 (1998) [hereinafter Merrill,
Right to Exclude]; Thomas W. Merrill & Henry E.
Smith,
What Happened to Property in Law and Economics?, 111 YALE L.J. 357, 364-66
(2001).
See generally Adam Mossoff, What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,
45 A
RIZ. L. REV. 371 (2003); Laura S. Underkuffler, On Property: An Essay, 100 YALE L.J.
127 (1990).
140
See Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in
Judicial Reasoning
, 26 YALE L.J. 710 (1917) [hereinafter Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal
Conceptions
]; Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as
Applied in Judicial Reasoning
, 23 YALE L.J. 16 (1913).
141
Felix S. Cohen, Dialogue on Private Property, 9 RUTGERS L. REV. 357, 361-63
(1954);
see also RESTATEMENT (FIRST) OF PROPERTY ch. 1, introductory cmt. (1936) (stating
that “[t]he word ‘propertyis used in this Restatement to denote legal relations between
persons with respect to a thing”); Wallace H. Hamilton & Irene Till,
Property, in 12
E
NCYCLOPAEDIA OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 528, 528 (Edwin R.A. Seligman & Alvin Johnson
eds., 1934) (defining “property” as “a euphonious collocation of letters which serves as a
general term for the miscellany of equities that persons hold in the commonwealth”);
Hohfeld,
Fundamental Legal Conceptions, supra note 140, at 743 (explaining that “the
supposed single right
in rem . . . really involves as many separate and distinct ‘right-duty’
relations as there are persons subject to a duty”).
716 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
scholars phrased as a “bundle of rights.”
142
Ultimately, if property reflects a
bundle of socially contingent rights, then the most essential right within this
bundle must be the
right to exclude others in society, a conclusion embraced
by many courts and scholars without question today.
143
This revolution impacted intellectual property as well.
144
Ultimately,
patents were defined solely as securing the right to exclude.
145
Courts and
scholars have justified the patent’s right to exclude on the grounds that it
provides an incentive to invent,
146
which achieves social utility by advancing
the constitutional purpose in promoting the useful arts.
147
In the nineteenth century, some courts and commentators presaged this
modern, post–legal realist view of patents,
148
but they did not reflect the
142
See, e.g., Kaiser Aetna v. United States, 444 U.S. 164, 176 (1979) (referring to “the
bundle of rights that are commonly characterized as property”); A
CKERMAN, supra note 12,
at 26-29 (discussing the “scientific” analysis of property as a “bundle” of rights).
143
See, e.g., Coll. Sav. Bank v. Fla. Prepaid Postsecondary Educ. Expense Bd., 527 U.S.
666, 673 (1999) (“The hallmark of a protected property interest is the right to exclude
others.”); Kaiser Aetna, 444 U.S. at 176 (stating that the right to exclude is “one of the most
essential sticks in the bundle of rights that are commonly characterized as property”);
Merrill, Right to Exclude, supra note 139, at 730 (“[T]he right to exclude others is more
than just ‘one of the most essential’ constituents of property – it is the
sine qua non.”).
144
See Mossoff, supra note 139, at 413-27 (discussing the impact of legal realists’ re-
conceptualization of property on myriad intellectual property doctrines).
145
See 35 U.S.C. § 154(a)(1) (2000) (stating that a patent secures “the right to exclude
others from making, using, offering for sale, or selling the invention”); Connell v. Sears,
Roebuck & Co., 722 F.2d 1542, 1548 (Fed. Cir. 1983) (“[A] patent is a form of property
right, and the right to exclude recognized in a patent is but the essence of the concept of
property.”); Carl Schenck, A.G. v. Nortron Corp., 713 F.2d 782, 786 n.3 (Fed. Cir. 1983)
(“The patent right is but the right to exclude others, the very definition of ‘property.’”);
see
also
FRANK Y. GLADNEY, RESTRAINTS OF TRADE IN PATENTED ARTICLES 18 (1910)
(describing the “patent law right” as solely the right to “exclude others from making, using
and selling” the patented invention); Dan L. Burk & Mark A. Lemley,
Policy Levers in
Patent Law
, 89 VA. L. REV. 1575, 1665 (2003) (remarking that “the patent right to exclude
has been regarded as a nearly absolute property rule”); Frank H. Easterbrook,
Intellectual
Property Is Still Property
, 13 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POLY 108, 109 (1990) (“Patents give a
right to exclude, just as the law of trespass does with real property.”); F. Scott Kieff & Troy
A. Paredes, The Basics Matter: At the Periphery of Intellectual Property, 73 GEO. WASH. L.
R
EV. 174, 198 (2004) (explaining that “patents only give a right to exclude” and that any
“right to use is derived from sources external to IP law”).
146
See, e.g., Rebecca S. Eisenberg, Patents and the Progress of Science: Exclusive
Rights and Experimental Use
, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1017, 1024-28 (1989); Edmund W. Kitch,
The Nature and Function of the Patent System, 20 J.L. & ECON. 265 (1977).
147
See, e.g., Bonito Boats, Inc. v. Thunder Craft Boats, Inc., 489 U.S. 141, 146-47
(1989); Graham v. John Deere Co., 383 U.S. 1, 5-6 (1966).
148
See, e.g., Bloomer v. McQuewan, 55 U.S. (14 How.) 539, 549 (1852) (explaining that
patents represent only a “right to exclude” others from this special “franchise” grant); Am.
Hide & Leather Splitting & Dressing Mach. Co. v. Am. Tool & Mach. Co., 1 F. Cas. 647,
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 717
dominant view of patents as property.
149
The first four patent statutes defined
patents as property in substantive terms as the exclusive rights to make, use
and dispose of one’s invention.
150
Nineteenth-century courts also defined
patents as express legal titles by which “inventors shall exclusively enjoy, for a
limited season, the fruits of their inventions,” by “authorizing them alone to
manufacture, sell, or practice what they have invented.”
151
It was this
conception of patents that linked them conceptually with other tangible
property entitlements.
152
In this way, courts sought to secure a patentee’s
651 (C.C.D. Mass. 1870) (No. 302) (stating that a patent is based only in “a statutory right, a
public grant of a monopoly”); Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (Aug. 13,
1813), in 13 THE WRITINGS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 326, 334-35 (Andrew A. Lipscomb &
Albert Ellery Bergh eds., 1905) (declaring that the “embarrassment of an exclusive patent”
was justified only because these “monopolies of invention” served the “benefit of society”).
149
See generally Mossoff, Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege, supra note 11
(surveying nineteenth-century case law, treatises, and commentary on the nature of patents
as property).
150
See Patent Act of 1870, ch. 230, § 22, 16 Stat. 198, 201 (repealed 1952) (providing
that “every patent shall contain a short title or description of the invention or discovery,
correctly indicating its nature and design, and a grant to the patentee, his heirs or assigns, for
the term of seventeen years, of the exclusive right to make, use, and vend the said invention
or discovery throughout the United States and the Territories thereof”); Patent Act of 1836,
ch. 357, § 11, 5 Stat. 117, 121 (repealed 1870) (providing that “every patent shall be
assignable in law” and that this “conveyance of the exclusive right under any patent, to
make and use, and to grant to others to make and use, the thing patented” must be recorded
in the Patent Office); Patent Act of 1793, ch. 11, § 1, 1 Stat. 318, 321 (repealed 1836)
(providing that a patent secures “the full and exclusive right and liberty of making,
constructing, using, and vending to others to be used, the said invention or discovery”);
Patent Act of 1790, ch. 7, § 1, 1 Stat. 109, 110 (repealed 1793) (providing that a patent
secures “the sole and exclusive right and liberty of making, constructing, using and vending
to others to be used, the said invention or discovery”).
151
Clark Patent Steam & Fire Regulator Co. v. Copeland, 5 F. Cas. 987, 988
(C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1862) (No. 2,866);
see also Birdsall v. McDonald, 3 F. Cas. 441, 444
(C.C.N.D. Ohio 1874) (No. 1,434) (“Inventors are a meritorious class of men. . . . Their
patents are their title deeds, and they should be construed in a fair and liberal spirit . . . .”);
Earth Closet Co. v. Fenner, 8 F. Cas. 261, 263 (C.C.D.R.I. 1871) (No. 4,249) (explaining
that a “patent is prima facie proof of title”); Evans v. Kremer, 8 F. Cas. 874, 875 (C.C.D. Pa.
1816) (No. 4,565) (explaining that a plaintiff-patentee must “be prepared to maintain his
title, in relation to the question of original discovery”).
152
See, e.g., McKeon v. Bisbee, 9 Cal. 137, 143 (1858) (“Property is the exclusive right
of possessing, enjoying, and disposing of a thing.”); Eaton v. Boston, Concord & Montreal
R.R., 51 N.H. 504, 511 (1872) (“‘Property is the right of any person to possess, use, enjoy,
and dispose of a thing.’” (quoting Wynehamer v. People, 13 N.Y. 378, 433 (1856)));
In re
Flintham, 11 Serg. & Rawle 16, 24 (Pa. 1823) (“Property without the power of use and
disposition is an empty sound.”); W
ILLIAM BLACKSTONE, 1 COMMENTARIES *138 (“The third
absolute right . . . is that of property: which consists in the free use, enjoyment, and disposal
of all his acquisitions . . . .”); STEPHEN MARTIN LEAKE & A.E. RANDALL, AN ELEMENTARY
DIGEST OF THE LAW OF PROPERTY IN LAND 1 (2d ed. 1909) (“Rights to things, jura in rem,
718 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
“substantive rights” the “right to manufacture, the right to sell, and the right
to use” the patented invention.
153
In sum, the patent was the legal means for
inventors to reap what they had sown, because invention “requires mind,
ingenuity, labor, time, and expense” in researching and developing a new idea
that succeeds in both practical application and in the marketplace.
154
This nineteenth-century conception of patents as serving to reward labor and
remunerate the expense of inventive activities reflected a more substantive
conception of property dominant at that time. It was a moral concept and legal
right predicated on the labor-based theories of the natural rights philosophers.
As Daniel Webster declared in the House of Representatives in 1824:
And, at this time of day, and before this Assembly, . . . he need not argue
that the right of the inventor is a high property; it is the fruit of his mind –
it belongs to him more than any other property he does not inherit it
he takes it by no man’s gift – it peculiarly belongs to him, and he ought to
be protected in the enjoyment of it.
155
Patents certainly served the complementary policy of promoting scientific
progress,
156
but patent law was not shielded from the influence exerted on
have for their subject some material thing, as land or goods, which the owner may use or
dispose of in any manner he pleases within the limits prescribed by the terms of his right.”);
see also Mossoff, supra note 139, at 403-39 (discussing the substantive conception of
property that was dominant in the nineteenth century and which encompassed the
possessory rights of acquisition, use, and disposal).
153
Adams v. Burke, 84 U.S. 453, 456 (1873).
154
Buck v. Hermance, 4 F. Cas. 550, 555 (C.C.N.D.N.Y. 1849) (No. 2,082) (Nelson,
Circuit Justice);
see also Birdsall, 3 F. Cas. at 444 (“Patent laws are founded on the policy
of giving to [inventors] remuneration for the fruits, enjoyed by others, of their labor and
their genius.”); Page v. Ferry, 18 F. Cas. 979, 983 (C.C.E.D. Mich. 1857) (No. 10,662)
(“The exclusive privilege is not conferred merely as a reward of genius, and for the
encouragement of useful inventions and improvements in arts and manufactures, but also
embraces the public benefit.”); Brooks v. Bicknell, 4 F. Cas. 247, 251 (C.C.D. Ohio 1843)
(No. 1,944) (McLean, Circuit Justice) (stating that “a man should be secured in the fruits of
his ingenuity and labor,” and that “it seems difficult to draw a distinction between the fruits
of mental and physical labor”); Blanchard v. Sprague, 3 F. Cas. 648, 650 (C.C.D. Mass.
1839) (No. 1,518) (Story, Circuit Justice) (explaining that patents are no longer regarded in
England or America as monopolies, but rather “[p]atents for inventions are now treated as a
just reward to ingenious men, and as highly beneficial to the public”).
155
41 ANNALS OF CONG. 934 (1824). Webster’s primary interlocutor in this House
debate was Representative Buchanan, who agreed with Webster that the law should “protect
the just rights of patentees” by securing “the property which an inventor has in that which is
the product of his own genius.”
Id. at 936.
156
Cf. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 212 n.18 (2003) (emphasizing in copyright law
the historical “complementary” relationship between the dual policies of rewarding labor
and promoting the progress of new creative works).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 719
nineteenth-century legal doctrines generally by the natural rights conception of
property.
157
For these reasons, it was common for nineteenth-century courts to draw
doctrinal and policy connections between traditional, tangible property rights
and patents.
158
The Campbell court’s declaration in the late 1870s that the
“property in a patented invention stands the same as other property” was
hardly a novel or controversial claim.
159
As early as 1846, juries were
instructed in patent infringement trials that “[a]n inventor holds a property in
his invention by as good a title as the farmer holds his farm and flock.”
160
If
the government trespassed on a farm or confiscated a farmer’s flock of geese,
then the property owner could sue under the relevant state or federal
constitutional provision.
161
Nineteenth-century federal courts, such as in
Burns, Cammeyer, McKeever, and Campbell, embraced the logical application
of such reasoning to patents: if the federal government trespassed on a
patentee’s property through the unauthorized use of a patented invention if
the government committed “piracy
162
then the patentee should have the
same right to sue for satisfaction under the Takings Clause.
157
See generally Claeys, supra note 13; Mossoff, supra note 139, at 427-38; Mossoff,
Reevaluating the Patent “Privilege,” supra note 11.
158
See supra notes 54-56 and accompanying text.
159
Campbell v. James, 4 F. Cas. 1168, 1172 (C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1879) (No. 2,361) (citing
Burns and Cammeyer).
160
Hovey v. Henry, 12 F. Cas. 603, 604 (C.C.D. Mass. 1846) (No. 6,742). A year
earlier, Justice Woodbury would embrace this same justification for classifying patents as
property:
“[A] liberal construction is to be given to a patent, and inventors sustained, if
practicable, . . . [as] only in this way can we protect intellectual property, the labors of
the mind, productions and interests as much a man’s own, and as much the fruit of his
honest industry, as the wheat he cultivates, or the flocks he rears.”
Davoll v. Brown, 7 F. Cas. 197, 199 (C.C.D. Mass. 1845) (No. 3,662). This was the first
time an American court used the phrase “intellectual property” in a patent law decision.
See
Justin Hughes, Copyright and Incomplete Historiographies: Of Piracy, Propertization, and
Thomas Jefferson
, 79 S. CAL. L. REV. 993, 1006 & n.39 (2006).
161
See, e.g., Pumpelly v. Green Bay Co., 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 166, 181 (1871) (holding
that “where real estate is actually invaded by superinduced additions of water, earth, sand,
or other material . . . so as to effectually destroy or impair its usefulness, it is a taking,
within the meaning of the Constitution”); Gardner v. Trustees of Newburgh, 2 Johns. Ch.
162, 165 (N.Y. Ch. 1816) (Kent, Chancellor) (holding that a riparian owner has a “right to
the use and enjoyment of the stream of water” that requires just compensation if interfered
with by the government).
162
See, e.g., Am. Diamond Rock Boring Co. v. Sullivan Mach. Co., 1 F. Cas. 641, 643
(C.C.S.D.N.Y. 1877) (No. 298) (recognizing that a mechanical equivalent “is a piracy of the
principle, and a violation of the patent”); Page v. Ferry, 18 F. Cas. 979, 985 (C.C.E.D. Mich.
1857) (No. 10,662) (charging the jury that if the defendant’s machine “obtained by
mechanical equivalents [the same result as plaintiff-patentee’s invention], it would certainly
constitute an infringement” because “it is a piracy of the principle”); Goodyear v. Cent. R.
720 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
This connection between tangible property and patents is evident only
insofar as one enters the conceptually distinct world of the nineteenth century,
which operated within a different analytical framework in adjudicating both
patent and property rights. This suggests an answer to the question posed at
the very beginning of this Article: Why are modern courts and scholars so
consistently wrong about the historical protection of patents as constitutional
private property? The answer, at least in part, may be that they are unable to
see the historical jurisprudence given the vast conceptual divide between the
legal-realist twentieth century and the natural-rights nineteenth century.
In our post–legal realist world, scholars and courts have excluded from the
legal definition of patents the use-rights necessary to conclude that
unauthorized uses by the government necessarily violate a patentee’s
constitutional private property under the Takings Clause. This tendency is
evident not only in patent law, but also in the takings jurisprudence that has
developed in the land cases that have dominated the Court’s docket in the past
few decades. In these cases, the Court has followed modern property theory
lockstep, focusing on the
right to exclude as the primary right in the bundle of
rights that it secures as constitutional private property.
163
In the world of
tangible property rights, the right to exclude is breached by a trespass a
physical dispossession from one’s land.
164
Accordingly, the Court consistently
uses
dispossession as evidence for a breach of the right to exclude, which is
Co., 10 F. Cas. 664, 667 (C.C.D.N.J. 1853) (No. 5,563) (Grier, Circuit Justice) (stating that
the defendant, who had made minor variations in the plaintiff’s patented product, was
“pirating the plaintiff’s invention”); Moody v. Fiske, 17 F. Cas. 655, 656-57 (C.C.D. Mass.
1820) (No. 9,745) (Story, Circuit Justice) (referring repeatedly to infringers of both patents
and copyrights as “pirates”); c
f. Davis v. Palmer, 7 F. Cas. 154, 159 (C.C.D. Va. 1827) (No.
3,645) (Marshall, Circuit Justice) (instructing the jury that if “the imitator attempted to copy
the [patented] model” and made an “almost imperceptible variation for the purpose of
evading the right of the patentee,” then “this may be considered as a fraud on the law”);
Dixon v. Moyer, 7 F. Cas. 758, 759 (C.C.D. Pa. 1821) (No. 3,931) (Washington, Circuit
Justice) (explaining that an attempt to make a “mere formal difference” between a patented
device and an infringing copy is “a fraudulent evasion of the plaintiff’s right”).
163
See, e.g., Coll. Sav. Bank v. Fla. Prepaid Postsecondary Educ. Expense Bd., 527 U.S.
666, 673 (1999) (“The hallmark of a protected property interest is the right to exclude
others.”); Dolan v. City of Tigard, 512 U.S. 374, 384 (1994) (declaring that right to exclude
is the essential right in a protected property interest); Kaiser Aetna v. United States, 444
U.S. 164, 176 (1979) (stating that the right to exclude is “one of the most essential sticks in
the bundle of rights that are commonly characterized as property”).
164
See Jacque v. Steenberg Homes, Inc., 563 N.W.2d 154, 159 (Wis. 1997) (explaining
that the “landowner’s interest in protecting his or her land from trespass” derives from the
fact that the “right to exclude others” is an essential property right); J
ESSE DUKEMINIER ET
AL
., PROPERTY 86 (6th ed. 2006) (“The law of trespass . . . protects the right to exclude
. . . .”); J
OSEPH WILLIAM SINGER, INTRODUCTION TO PROPERTY 27 (2001) (“The interest
protected by trespass law is the interest in exclusive possession of the premises, meaning the
right to occupy the property and to exclude others from entering or occupying the
property.”).
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 721
now the analytical fulcrum for determining a compensable taking by the
government, either directly through a condemnation or physical invasion
165
or
indirectly through a regulation that results in something equivalent to
dispossession.
166
Given its status as intellectual property, a patent is nonrivalrous and
nonexhaustive in nature.
167
The government’s unauthorized use of a patented
invention, therefore, lacks the
physical dispossession that triggers a
compensable taking of land.
168
From the perspective of land-based takings
doctrine, the government’s unauthorized use of a patented invention does not
interfere with a patentee’s own use of the invention, and, more importantly, the
patentee can continue to exclude others from using it.
169
What then could a patentee claim as a taking when the government uses a
patented invention without authorization? A patentee could only claim some
165
See Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp., 458 U.S. 419, 434 (1982)
(holding that any “permanent physical occupation of property” by the state is a taking).
166
Modern regulatory takings jurisprudence is highly indeterminate and “ad hoc.” Penn
Cent. Transp. Co. v. New York City, 438 U.S. 104, 124 (1978). The Court, however,
consistently uses dispossession as evidence for a breach of the right to exclude in
determining whether a compensable regulatory taking has occurred.
See, e.g., Lingle v.
Chevron U.S.A., Inc., 544 U.S. 528, 539 (2005) (“A permanent physical invasion, however
minimal the economic cost it entails, eviscerates the owner’s right to exclude others from
entering and using her property perhaps the most fundamental of all property interests.”);
Lucas v. S.C. Coastal Council, 505 U.S. 1003, 1017 (1992) (holding that a “total deprivation
of beneficial use is, from the landowner’s point of view, the equivalent of a physical
appropriation”); Ruckelshaus v. Monsanto Co., 467 U.S. 986, 1011 (1984) (holding that a
regulation that discloses a trade secret is a taking because “the right to exclude others is
central to the very definition of the property interest”);
Penn Cent. Transp. Co., 438 U.S. at
124 (recognizing that “[a] ‘taking’ may more readily be found when the interference with
property can be characterized as a physical invasion by government”).
167
See, e.g., Burk & Lemley, supra note 145, at 1605 (stating that “information is a
public good for which consumption is nonrivalrous – that is, one person’s use of the
information does not deprive others of the ability to use it”); Katherine J. Strandburg, What
Does the Public Get? Experimental Use and the Patent Bargain
, 2004 WIS. L. REV. 81, 104
(observing that “ideas are nonexcludable public goods”). This is not a modern insight.
See
Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson, supra note 148, at 334 (stating that
inventive ideas are like “the air in which we breathe, move, and have our physical being,
incapable of confinement or exclusive appropriation”).
168
See Heald & Wells, supra note 35, at 868 (“Intellectual property is intangible, and
therefore it is incapable of being physically possessed or taken away.”); Klancnik,
supra
note 34, at 817 (recognizing that “a government mandate cannot amount to a physical taking
of the patent because the government cannot occupy an intangible, legal construct the way it
can physically occupy land”).
169
See Wilmoth, supra note 34, at 565 (“The State can put a patent to public use without
eliminating the patentee’s ability to use the patent himself. In such event, a patentee can
still gather fruits of his labor, prevent nongovernmental competitors from infringing, or
license or transfer his right to others.”).
722 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
lost profits resulting from this governmental action. Zoltek, for instance,
pursued financial remuneration – its reasonable royalty for the government’s
unauthorized use of its patented method for making composite fiber sheets
used in aircraft construction.
170
However, the Supreme Court has held, at least
since the legal realists’ heyday in the early twentieth century, that the loss of
only some uses or profits almost never amounts to a taking.
171
In rejecting a
takings claim on the basis of lost profits in the use of tangible property, the
Supreme Court has intoned that “loss of future profits – unaccompanied by any
physical property restriction provides a slender reed upon which to rest a
takings claim.”
172
It is these future profits the right to the fruits of one’s
labors that a patentee would assert under a Takings Clause claim today. In
fact, long before
Zoltek, modern courts employed such reasoning in rejecting
patent takings claims on the basis of lost profits.
173
According to our modern view of patents, which secures solely the right to
exclude and nothing else, governmental interferences with commercial uses of
patents could not fall within the scope of “private propertysecured under the
Constitution.
174
Accordingly, if the government remunerates patentees for its
own unauthorized uses, the government is not implementing a constitutional
mandate under the Takings Clause. Rather, it is doing so at the sole policy
discretion of Congress, which amended the Tucker Act in 1910 to include the
government within the scope of the exclusive right that it already secured
under the patent statutes.
175
In fact, Judge Dyk emphasized this point
170
See Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 442 F.3d 1345, 1347-49 (Fed. Cir. 2006).
171
See, e.g., Tahoe-Sierra Pres. Council, Inc. v. Tahoe Reg’l Planning Agency, 535 U.S.
302 (2002) (holding that a local government moratorium on all development of land for
thirty-two months is not a compensable taking); Palazzolo v. Rhode Island, 533 U.S. 606
(2001) (holding that a regulation that eliminated approximately ninety-three percent of the
value of a land parcel did not deprive the owner of all economically beneficial uses); Lucas,
505 U.S. at 1027 (“It seems to us that the property owner necessarily expects the uses of his
property to be restricted, from time to time, by various measures newly enacted by the State
in legitimate exercise of its police powers.”); Pa. Coal Co. v. Mahon, 260 U.S. 393, 413
(1922) (Holmes, J.) (“Government hardly could go on if to some extent values incident to
property could not be diminished without paying for every such change in the general
law.”).
172
Andrus v. Allard, 444 U.S. 51 (1979) (rejecting a regulatory takings claim on the
basis of a federal prohibition on the sale of eagle feathers).
173
See Mosca v. United States, 417 F.2d 1382, 1386 (Ct. Cl. 1969) (rejecting a patent
takings claim on the basis that “[t]here is . . . grave doubt as to whether . . . earning profits in
the future is property within the contemplation of the Fifth Amendment,” as it is already
“well established that profits to be derived from a business conducted on property that it
[sic] taken by the Government are not considered as [constitutional private] property”).
174
What might be most surprising to patent scholars today is that this observation is
consistent with the Court’s takings jurisprudence governing land and other tangible property
interests.
175
See supra notes 121, 124-34 and accompanying text.
2007] PATENTS AS CONSTITUTIONAL PRIVATE PROPERTY 723
repeatedly in his multiple concurrences in
Zoltek.
176
The Zoltek decision
stands as a stark reminder of how this conclusion seems almost inevitable
within the mutually reinforcing frameworks of modern property theory and
modern takings jurisprudence.
177
This analysis is not a definitive, comprehensive intellectual history of
patents and property, but it illuminates an important aspect of the jurisprudence
that is often overlooked: the way that courts and scholars define legal rights
affects their ability to identify and to understand relevant aspects of the
historical record.
178
Courts sometimes recognize the import of this insight, at
least in the abstract. For instance, Judge Dyk himself remarked in a patent
infringement case a few years ago that “[p]atent law is not an island separated
from the main body of American jurisprudence.”
179
Unfortunately, Judge Dyk overlooked this important principle when he
joined the
Zoltek majority in refusing to apply the Takings Clause to patents –
based on his faulty understanding of the historical record. In fact, in his
Zoltek
concurrence, Judge Dyk argued that “[p]atent rights are creatures of federal
statute,” and thus Congress is free to provide whatever remedies it sees fit
without constitutional limitation
180
– an argument explicitly rejected more than
a century ago in
Burns, Cammeyer, McKeever, and Campbell.
181
Several
months later, Judge Dyk repeated the same (historically mistaken) point in his
concurrence to the Federal Circuit’s denial of Zoltek’s petition for rehearing en
176
Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 464 F.3d 1335, 1339 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (Dyk, J.,
concurring); Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 442 F.3d 1345, 1367-70 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (Dyk,
J., concurring).
177
There is some evidence that the Court may at least be aware implicitly that the logic
of its regulatory takings doctrine, as applied in land cases, leads inexorably to a conclusion
that there could never be a taking of an intangible property right. See generally Eric R.
Claeys,
The Penn Central Test and Tensions in Liberal Property Theory, 30 HARV. ENVTL.
L. R
EV. 339, 362-65 (2006) (examining differences between the Court’s treatment of takings
of intangible interests, such as a trade secret or the right to devise, from its treatment of
takings of land). Exploring such theoretical issues is beyond the scope of the current
Article, but Professor Claeys and I hope to develop this insight in greater depth in a future
project.
178
The sources relied on in this Article provide, directly or indirectly, some more
extensive treatment of these issues.
See supra notes 11, 139, 157; see also Robert G. Bone,
A New Look at Trade Secret Law: Doctrine in Search of Justification, 86 CAL. L. REV. 241,
259 (1998) (observing an analogous trend in the context of trade secrets doctrine whereby
its supporting theory in the nineteenth century “began to lose its grip, first with the rise of
sociological jurisprudence, and then with the advent of legal realism in the early twentieth
century”).
179
Knorr-Bremse Systeme Fuer Nutzfahrzeuge GMBH v. Dana Corp., 383 F.3d 1337,
1351 (Fed. Cir. 2004) (en banc) (Dyk, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
180
Zoltek, 442 F.3d at 1370 (Dyk, J., concurring).
181
See supra Part II.
724 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:689
banc.
182
Why is Judge Dyk seemingly unaware of this long-standing
jurisprudence that directly contradicts his claims concerning the constitutional
status of patent property rights? Perhaps he misses it given that the analytical
and normative framework employed by the courts in
Burns, Cammeyer,
McKeever, and Campbell are no longer cognizable to a modern jurist or
scholar. As this Part has shown, historical developments in American
jurisprudence may affect how courts and scholars understand the history of
patent rights.
C
ONCLUSION
In its recent decision in eBay v. MercExchange,
183
the Supreme Court
emphasized that modern patent law jurisprudence should not depart from long-
standing historical practices.
184
eBay is important for many reasons, but not
the least is that it highlights the degree to which modern patent policy debates
are predicated on the history of patent law.
185
Yet, despite this heavy emphasis
on history by courts and scholars alike, there remain surprisingly resilient
historical myths, and one of them is that patents were never secured as
constitutional private property in the nineteenth century.
This Article has revealed that this historical claim is mistaken, and that
courts and scholars are relying on it to justify limiting the scope of
constitutional protections afforded to patents today. Unfortunately, the modern
conceptualization of patents as securing only the right to exclude has blinded
modern courts and scholars to the extensive nineteenth-century jurisprudence
that protected patents as constitutional private property. The result is
confusion among courts, and inaccurate claims made in both patent and takings
scholarship, that patents have never been secured under the Takings Clause.
Courts and scholars can no longer rely on this mistaken historical authority. It
is time to set the historical record straight and to recognize that nineteenth-
century courts applied the Takings Clause to patents, securing these intangible
property rights as constitutional private property.
182
See Zoltek Corp. v. United States, 464 F.3d 1335, 1339 (Fed. Cir. 2006) (Dyk, J.,
concurring) (“This decided lack of interest by the Congress and the Supreme Court in
creating a takings remedy is perhaps not surprising given the fact that patent rights are
created only by federal statute . . . .”).
183
126 S. Ct. 1837 (2006).
184
Id. at 1839-40.
185
This is especially salient in Chief Justice Roberts’ admonition in eBay that nineteenth-
century jurisprudence is determinative in defining the scope of legal rights today.
Id. at
1841-42 (Roberts, C.J., concurring).